Friday, May 21, 2021


Introduction to Marxism and the Philosophy of Science

Stamp_of_ussr_0977-
1945 stamp celebrating the 220th anniversary of the Russian Academy of Sciences. via Wikimedia Commons.

Set 15 of our Radical Thinkers series brings together four classic works in the history of science. Helena Sheehan's Marxism and the Philosophy of Science: A Critical History, first published in 1985 and revised in 1993, offers a detailed survey of the Marxist philosophies of science developed in the hundred years between Marx's and Engels' work of the 1840s and the end of World War II. Below we present Sheehan's introduction to the first edition of the book.

 
9781786634269

“Sheehan’s book remains the single best secondary analysis of the debates over Marxist philosophy of science from its creation in the late nineteenth century … until the close of World War II. It is an indispensable reference to the polyglot efflorescence of dialectical materialist thought across Europe, with especial emphasis on writings in German, Russian, and English, though she impressively ventures even farther afield. It is essential reading for anyone interested in these questions.”


In these pages, there unfolds a complex and intricate story. Although it is a story of the most vital significance, it has long been left untold. In some quarters this has been because of a total ignorance that there was anything to tell, and in other quarters because of a fear of the telling of it. It is the story of the shifting nexus of science, philosophy, and politics within Marxism. It is astonishing to discover in how many different ways and on how many different levels these have converged within the development of the Marxist tradition, both for better and for worse, with a multiplicity of factors coming into play, including the impact of new scientific discoveries, new philosophical trends and new political formations upon the overall process. While it is a story of a progressive and audacious enterprise, to which intelligent and discerning minds have applied themselves, it is also a story with its dark side, with retrogressive episodes, unscrupulous characters, hasty and ill-conceived projects, and superficial solutions, sometimes with dire consequences.

This work attempts to give a historical account of the development of Marxism as a philosophy of science, as well as a philosophical analysis of the issues involved. This volume encompasses the first hundred years of the existence of Marxism, beginning with the mid-1840s when the philosophical ideas of Marx and Engels began to emerge in mature form, and ending with the mid-1940s with the dissolution of the Comintern and the end of the Second World War. It deals both with the mainstream of the Marxist tradition in the development of dialectical materialism as a philosophy of science and with the diverging currents advocating alternative philosophical positions. It shows the Marxist tradition to be far more complex and differentiated than is usually imagined, characterized by sharp and lively controversies for contending paths of development at every step of the way.

The debates about how to develop Marxism as a philosophy of science have taken a number of forms. One recurring theme has been that of the precise relationship between philosophy and the actual results of the empirical sciences, debated in the sharpest form in the controversy between the mechanists and dialecticians in the Soviet 1920s. Another recurring theme has been the relationship of specific scientific discoveries to the philosophy of dialectical materialism, such as the controversies over relativity theory or genetics (the much cited “Lysenko affair"). Yet another theme has been whether dialectical materialism or alternative philosophies of science, based on neo-Kantianism, Machism, or mechanistic materialism, are the most appropriate development of the Marxist tradition, such alternatives having been put forward by the Austro-Marxists, the Russian empirio-criticists and the Soviet mechanists. There have also been debates about whether to develop Marxism as a philosophy of science, disputes exemplified most sharply by the emergence of the neo-Hegelian trend within Marxism and the dialectics of nature debate set off by the Hungarian Marxist Lukács in the Comintern in the 1920s and continuing into the 1970s.

It all adds up to a formidable intellectual tradition in the philosophy of science which is virtually ignored by academic philosophy of science outside Eastern Europe. Certainly in the world of Anglo-American philosophy departments, insofar as there is any thought given to the history of the philosophy of science, in this era in which philosophy has become so woefully ahistorical, it is fixated on one line of development. The consensus undoubtedly is that the main dramatis personnae of nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophy of science are such as Mach, Carnap, Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend. This line of development has constituted the point of reference to which all commentators are expected to orient themselves, no matter how fundamental their criticisms of it, no matter how deep their commitment to charting a new way forward. I do not doubt that this line of development has been a vitally important one and that anyone working in this discipline without a thorough knowledge of the history of its major shifts and its present-day twists and turns would deserve harsh judgement from his or her colleagues. My point, however, is to call attention to the fact, too often neglected in this milieu, that this is not in fact the only major line of development in nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophy of science.

Another line of development, stemming from the very bold and original work of Marx and Engels, has been one with a very different relationship to both philosophy and science, but with, nevertheless, its own full-blown tradition in the philosophy of science — its own history, its own shifts, its own very fascinating twists and turns. However, no one is judged badly by his or her colleagues for being utterly oblivious of it and those who bother to think of it at all consider the sideward glances at Marxism on the part of Popper and Lakatos to be as much as it deserves, despite the fact that these forays have not been characterized by very full knowledge or very high standards of argument. Its history is known hardly at all and only the vaguest of caricatures of it prevail, with the name most readily connected with it almost inevitably being that of Lysenko. Lysenko has been part of it, to be sure, but so indeed have Marx, Engels, Lenin, Bukharin, Deborin, Bernal, Haldane, Caudwell, Langevin, Prenant, Geymonat, Hessen, Oparin, Fok, Ambartsumian, Kedrov, Hollitscher, and many others. Nor is it, as such names should indicate, simply an Eastern European phenomenon. It made, for example, significant inroads even into the hallowed Royal Society in 1930s Britain.

Although these two traditions have struggled with many of the same issues, the basic rhythms of their development have been very different. The tradition stemming from Mach and the Vienna Circle arose out of the impulse to defend scientific rationality in the face of the challenges posed to it by new developments in science. In an atmosphere of crisis in the epistemological foundations of science, with all forms of rampant obscurantism feeding off this crisis, they strove to set science upon secure foundations. They sought to purify and cleanse the intellectual inheritance of the ages of all superfluous accretions, to clear out the slag of the centuries, to subject all belief to the clear light of reason and the rigor of experiment. They did so, however, from a base that was too narrow, employing criteria that were too restricted, leaving out of the picture too much that was all too real. Rigidly separating the context of discovery from the context of justification, the logical positivist and logical empiricist schools took only the latter to be the proper concern of the philosophy of science. The process by which a theory came to be was irrelevant to judgements on its validity. And, if psychological, sociological, and historical considerations were irrelevant, metaphysical considerations were worse than irrelevant. The striving for a comprehensive world view, giving rise to the great basic questions of the history of philosophy, was renounced in no uncertain terms.

The trajectory of this tradition, from positivism to the current variety of postpositivist philosophies of science, has reflected the pressure of a complex reality upon conceptions too restricted to give an adequate account of it. The successive modifications of the tradition over the years, from verificationism to falsification, to the historicism of paradigm shifts, to the methodology of scientific research programs, to methodological dadaism, have been impressive but still inadequate attempts to come to terms with the metaphysical and historical dimensions of science. Despite such significant departures from the antimetaphysical and ahistorical heritage of the Vienna Circle, it still cannot be said that philosophers of science have yet brought to bear the full weight of the implications of metaphysics or historicity for science. Moreover, insofar as these dimensions have come into play, they have tended to do so in a negative way, in that they have been perceived as undermining the rationality of science. Many of the current debates are rooted in a persistent inability to reconcile the rationality of science with the metaphysical and sociohistorical character of science. In a strange way, the residues positivism linger on and color the views of even the most radical of antipositivists. And the flames of the crisis in the epistemological foundations of science bum more wildly than ever. There is no consensus, indeed there is exceedingly sharp polarization, regarding the relationship of science either to philosophy or to history.

It has always seemed somewhat ironic to me that the most influential line of development in breaking with classical empiricism in the direction of a more contextual, sociohistorical, metaphysical view of science has come via Wittgenstein and Kuhn, when there were earlier bodies of thought already there, which had long since put forward far deeper and more radical critiques of the received view of science and far richer alternative versions. Both the radical empiricist tradition of James and Dewey and the dialectical materialist tradition of generations of Marxists have embodied attemative versions of empiricism (in the sense of seeing the origins of knowledge in experience), which were based on much richer notions of experience, which allowed the metaphysical and historical dimensions of knowledge to come more fully into play. Both rejected the formalist, individualist, particularist, passivist model of knowledge in favor of a more historicist, social, contextualist, activist model. 

Long before Wittgenstein, these earlier thinkers understood that experience came already clothed in language; that meaning could only be understood in context; that no logical formalism could substitute for the real flow of actual experience. Long before Kuhn, they knew that science was a complex, social, human activity; that is, was a process characterized by both evolutionary development and revolutionary upheavals. Long before Popper, they spoke of the role of guessing in science; they criticized the view that science was a matter of straightforward induction and saw the part played by hypothesis and deduction. Long before the emergence of the Edinburgh School, they made very strong claims indeed about the role of social interests in knowledge; they believed sociological explanation to be relevant to all theories, whether in literature or science, whether true or false, rational or irrational. Indeed, so many contemporary themes, such as the role of theory in observation, the attention to the process of discovery as well as to the process of justification, the impossibility of strict verification, and many others, turn out to be antici­pated in these now dusty tomes on yellowed page after yellowed page. (Ludwig Fleck’s Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact (1979) is one such previously neglected text that has contemporary themes. Fleck used historical-epistemological categories like “thought-style” and “thought-collective,” and presented Wasserman’s test for syphilis to emphasize the plasticity of scientific “facts.”)

The differences, however, are just as striking. Both of these earlier traditions placed science within a much wider sociohistorical context than did Kuhn and his successors. They understood far better the relationship of the history of science to the history of everything else, which undercut the possibility of such protected worlds-unto-themselves as Wittgensteinian language games, Kuhnian paradigms, or Popperian third worlds. Their field of vision opened to a much wider world. Their understanding penetrated to a much deeper historicity. Their modes of thought were much more integral and so they were not prone to the one-sidedness of later views. Their realization of the importance of hypothesis and deduction did not lead them to deny any role whatsoever to induction. Their awareness of complexity did not lead them to conclude that there were no unifying patterns. Their historicism did not entail discontinuity. Their acceptance of relativity did not imply incommensurability. Their renunciation of the quest for certainty did not bring them to despair, to announcements of the “end of epistemology,” to declarations that “anything goes.” What is really most striking about these earlier thinkers is how much more robust they were; how much more able they were to live in an open, uncertain, unfinished universe with many risks and no guarantees; how much more willing they were to stake their lot with uncertified possibilities. Nothing in all that they knew about what a complicated and uncertain activity science was stopped them from taking their stand with science and even drawing farreaching conclusions from it.

Here I leave to someone else or to another day the task of making the case further for the radical empiricist tradition of American philosophy. This book and the one to follow will hopefully make the case for Marxism. Given the tensions wracking contemporary philosophy of science, it could well be of value to look back on a tradition that has proceeded with the same quite crucial matters, but in such a different way. The most significant features of Marxism in respect to these problems are: (1) that it has seen scientific theories as inextricably woven into world views; (2) that it has made extraordinarily strong claims regarding the sociohistorical character of scientific knowledge; (3) that it has not tended to perceive these aspects as being in any way in conflict with the rationality of science. Marx and Engels saw the history of science as unfolding in such a way that science was a cognitive activity carried on within the framework of a whole world view, which was in turn shaped by the nature of the socioeconomic order within which it emerged. Such a characterization of science took nothing away from science in their eyes. The science of the past, grounded in the world views of the past, grounded by the relations of production of the past, had all been necessary stages in the evolution of human understanding. It was necessary to unmask the superseded ideologies of the past and present that distorted the development of science. Even more, it was necessary to move the process onward to the next stage: the further development of science, in the context of a new world view, in the context of a struggle for a new social order and new relations of production.

From the beginning, the Marxist tradition bravely set itself the task of elaborating the philosophical implications of the sciences of its times with a view to working out a scientific Weltanschauung adequate for its epoch. Engels's antipositivist materialism was an extraordinarily impressive achievement. He did not shrink from the great basic questions that have perplexed the philosophers of the ages, but he did insist that attempts at answers be grounded in the best empirical knowledge of the time. In so doing, he not only laid the foundations of a scientifically grounded world view, but set forth views on many issues, such as reductionism, the history of science, and the logic of scientific discovery, that not only anticipated certain contemporary theories, but are still in advance of them. Throughout its subsequent history, there were new challenges to meet, arising out of the revolutionary advances in the natural sciences as well as out of the emergence of new philosophical trends and new political formations, and these giving rise at every step along the way to new controversies, new arguments for contending paths of development. It is a complex tradition, with Marcuse or Colletti as far from Engels as Feyerabend from Carnap.

Some of these contending paths involved explicit renunciation of Engels’s enterprise of striving for a comprehensive world view grounded in science and in continuity with the history of philosophy. There have been, for example, the Soviet mechanists who believed that science could do very well without philosophy, as well as Marxists of the neo-Hegelian variety who have tended to think that philosophy should keep its distance from science. Today, the interpretation of Marxism as a Weltanschauung tied to the development of science is by no means an uncontested position. It is no secret that there are today many contending schools of thought, all claiming to embody the correct interpretation of Marxism, some of which explicitly renounce the ideal of a Weltanschauung and display a marked hostility to the natural sciences, while others make a fetish out of an eccentric concept of science and tend to take a derogatory attitude to philosophy. Nevertheless, the mainstream of the Marxist tradition has defended the sort of synthesis of science and philosophy that Engels proposed, even it has not always proceeded in the best possible way to bring the project to fruition.

From the beginning as well, this whole project has been placed firmly within a wider socio historical context. Philosophy of science was no free-floating set of theories spontaneously thought up by free-floating philosophers of science. Nor was science a straightforward piling up of facts about the world unproblematically discovered by autonomous scientists in their sealed-off laboratories. Marxists have seen philosophy, science, and philosophy of science, and indeed all aspects of the intellectual culture, as all inextricably interwoven with each other and tied to a common social matrix. It is no accident that a whole distinct tradition in philosophy of science has emerged and developed in relation to such a distinct social theory and political movement as Marxism. Marxism made its entrance on the historical stage not only with its critique of capitalism, its labor theory of value, its materialist interpretation of history as class struggle, its call for socialist revolution. It also formulated in the same act the classical premises of the whole discipline of sociology of knowledge and the externalist tradition in the historiography of science. (The Marxist tradition has been seminal in the development of a whole cluster of disciplines, such as the sociology of knowledge, sociology of science, history of science, and history of technology, and has had a crucial influence even on their non-Marxist practitioners, such as Karl Mannheim and Robert Merton.)

The Marxist tradition has come forward with the fullest and most highly integrated claims to date regarding the socioeconomic basis of the rhythms of intellectual history. It is one of the most striking features of the story told in these pages just how tight its participants perceived the relation of science, philosophy, and politics to be, as far as both their own and their opponents’ theories were concerned. Marxism is therefore a tradition in which the relation of science to philosophy and of both to politics and economics is conceived of differently than in alternative traditions. The other traditions too have their socioeconomic basis, Marxists have argued, even if they have been unable to be fully self-conscious and explicit about it. Indeed, even the inability to rise to such self-consciousness and explicitness in this realm has a socioeconomic basis on this account.

There can be no doubt that Marxism has given rise to a multifaceted and protracted struggle, both creative and destructive, to confront the philosophical problems raised by probing into the role of ideology in relation to science and philosophy of science. There is much to be learned both from the profound insights and from the tragic disasters born of passionate debates revolving around the tensions between partisanship and truth, between "proletarian science" and laws of nature. It still cannot be said, however, that the fundamental philosophical problem has yet been satisfactorily and explicitly resolved by Marxists or by anyone else. The underlying question, still to be sharply answered, is: How can science be the complex, uncertain, precarious, human process that it is — inextricably bound up with all sorts of philosophical assumptions and with all sorts of wider sociohistorical processes — and still be reliable knowledge of nature? The story set out here does not give that question the sharp, clear, fully argued answer that we feel that it needs, but it does give much in the way of promise and indicates that the resources for that sort of answer may well be there.

In proceeding with this question ourselves, of course, we need to do our own thinking, but we should do it with a grounding in the best insights that all available intellectual traditions have to offer. The polarization, for or against Marxism, has been a formidable barrier to the sort of recriprocal interaction that could bear fruit.

This raises a recurring problem in the history of Marxism, i.e., the relation of Marxism to non-Marxist trends. This, it must be said, is a problem that Marxists have not always handled very well. Most have unfortunately gone to the one extreme or the other, either accommodating themselves too far in the direction of recurrences of modes of thought superseded by Marxism and compromising the very distinctiveness of Marxism beyond recognition without sufficient reason for doing so or considering Marxism a closed world, with nothing to leam from other schools of thought and heaping abuse and invective upon anyone who has suggested otherwise.

The traditions of Russian Marxism, with its tendency to identify opposition with treachery, and with its decided inability to be fair-minded towards opponents, has exercised a disproportionate influence in the latter direction. Even Lenin, who learned far more from non-Marxist ideas and was far more broad-minded than the subsequent generation of Russian Marxists, was notoriously unfair to Mach and Bogdanov. With lesser men, the exaggeration of the worst aspects of this tradition, backed by the powers of the NKVD (The Peoples Commissariat of Internal Affairs, the Soviet security police from 1934 to 1953, the predecessor of the KGB), has had disastrous and harrowing consequences. This has resulted in a hardening of the lines of debate between a fixed “orthodoxy” and a traitorous or martyred (depending on one’s point of view) "revisionism." 

This has led, on the one hand, to an unhealthy pressure against creative thinking and to a sterile adherence to fixed formulations. A nearly pathological fear of revisionism has obscured the fact that every tradition with the vitality to endure has revised and must continually revise itself with the onward march of history and with the progressive achievements of human knowledge. Marxists must judge matters on the basis of the evidence, on the basis of truth criteria established by the highest level of development of scientific method at any given time, and not on the basis of conformity or nonconformity to established Marxist premises, no matter how fundamental. Only if its most basic premises are continually scrutinized can the continued affirmation of them be meaningful. Of course, if really basic premises could no longer be affirmed in this way, then it would be legitimate to query whether the new position should still be considered Marxist. But only by being open to this possibility, by following Marx's own advice to question everything, can Marxism be adhered to and developed in a healthy way.

On the other hand, this rigidity has fanned the flames of opposition and polarized debate along unconstructive lines, resulting in the tendency of those who wanted to be creative and were repulsed by the rigidity to close their minds to any of the "orthodox" premises and to grasp eclectically and regressively at contradictory premises, sometimes just because they did contradict the orthodox ones. Political factors, which can either enhance or distort philosophical thinking, have often had such a distorting effect, insofar as theoretical judgements have been overshadowed both by administrative measures and antipathy to administrative measures. This being so, it is sad but true to say, as Marx Wartofsky has, that "communist politics, as well as anticommunist politics, left the tradition of Marxist scholarship enfeebled." 1

Nevertheless, the various "revisionist" positions bear a closer look than they have tended to get, either from those who have dismissed them out of hand or from those who have glorified them uncritically. Those, such as the early Lukács or the various Marxists of the Second International, who sought to bring back into Marxism the neo-Kantian dichotomy between history and nature, were, it could be argued, reverting to an antithesis already transcended by a higher synthesis. It meant dropping something crucial to Marxism as a higher and more integrated mode of thought. It did, however, highlight certain problems within Marxist thought, that is, the relationship between freedom and necessity, the relationship between the role of critical thought, ethical norms, and revolutionary activity on the one hand and the role of science and causal laws on the other. These were aspects of Marxist thought that needed to be clarified or further developed with the decline of the liberal idea of progress, the more problematic character of science, the turn from materialism with a new balance of class forces as the bourgeoisie turned from an alliance with the proletariat against the feudal aristocracy to making their peace with the right against the forces rising against them on the left. In the same way, the Machist interpretation of Marxism may have brought back a subjectivism superseded by the Marxist unity of subject and object, but it did reflect very real epistemological problems raised by the new level of development of scientific knowledge. It called attention to questions that needed to be posed and answered in a new way, on the basis of new knowledge and at a new level of sophistication.

This in turn raises many problems of historiography with which I had to grapple in writing this book and I have come to believe that it is vital to break from received patterns of interpretation in thinking about the history of Marxism:

      1. from seeing it as developing in an unproblematic straight line from its founders to today's Soviet textbooks of dialectical materialism, with every query along the way branded as an assault on the integrity of the tradition;

      2. from thinking it would have been an unproblematic straight line but for the "cult of personality";

      3. from grasping at the "classics of heresy," reading their propositions back into the works of Marx and writing off the rest as sheer dogmatism; 2

      4. from taking selected texts, which are given an exceedingly forced "reading," and making these entirely constitutive of what counts as Marxism, and dismissing any consideration outside that framework as "historicist"; 3

      5. from throwing the whole lot together as the "illusion of the epoch." 4

The history of Marxism insofar as it is written at all is, for the most part, written along the above lines. There is, to be sure, a healthy tradition in Marxist historiography, represented by such writers as Eric Hobsbawm, E.P. Thompson, and Christopher Hill, though little in the field of philosophy or philosophy of science. Bearing on this problematic under study here, there is very little that is relatively free of the above patterns of interpretation, the most notable exception being Loren Graham's Science and Philosophy in the Soviet Union (London, 1973). Graham, although not a Marxist, has given an extremely fair assessment of Soviet philosophy of science in a sympathetic but critical vein.

But almost all comprehensive or partial histories of Marxism bearing on philosophy and philosophy of science fit into the above categories, mostly into categories three and five. George Lichtheim's Marxism: A Historical and Critical Study (London, 1961) fits into the third category and only really covers the period to 1918, with only a sketchy and heavily caricatured concluding section dealing with the subsequent period. Gustav Wetter's Dialectical Materialism: A Historical and Systematic Study of Philosophy in the Soviet Union, complete with imprimatur and nihil obstat, falls into the fifth, as do a number of other such works written by neo-Thomist sovietologists, though it must be said that these are valuable as source material, the standards of scholarship being quite high, despite premises that rule out the possibility of sympathetic analysis. The most ambitious and seemingly comprehensive work to appear has been Leszek Kolakowski's three volume Main Currents of Marxism (London, 1978), a curious blend of the thinking associated with the third and fifth categories, reflecting the author's own growing dissociation with Marxism. The perspective from which he now seems to judge it all has been aptly described by Wartofsky in his review: "Between God, despair, and peaceful meliorism, Kolakowski offers no decisive choices, though he flirts with all three." 5 Whatever the merits of Kolakowski’s work, and merits there are, it suffers severely from his inability to give a fair account of positions with which he disagrees. There are also significant gaps that make it far from comprehensive. So too with David McLellan’s Marxism After Marx (London, 1979) which falls roughly into the third category and which is lacking in proportion and perspective and full of omissions and interpretations somewhat off the mark.

As for those connected with categories one, two, and four, there are inhibiting factors against writing such histories. In the case of the first and second, there is simply too much material in existence contradicting these interpretations and such efforts that forge ahead despite this are a combination of evasion or blatant fabrication. The most crass example was the famous Stalinist History of the CPSU(B): Short Course (Moscow, 1939). A more recent, toned-down, example is Mikhail Iovchuk’s Philosophical Traditions Today (Moscow, 1973).

The fact is that the history of Marxism has taken certain turns that present special problems in the matter of Marxist historiography. The history of Marxism is for many reasons dominated by the history of the communist movement. While noncommunists, for the most part anticommunists, have found this history almost impossible to comprehend, producing extremely distorted accounts of it, communists themselves have not helped much. For the stark truth of the matter is that communists have found it exceedingly difficult to be honest about their own history. (It must be said, however, that Western European communists have made serious efforts to overcome this in recent years.) Chapters four and five will try to give some indication why. In all events, precedents were set in the most deplorable degradation of intellectual life: Stalin’s denunciation of "archive rats," followed by a wave of denunciation of "rotten liberalism" and "bourgeois objectivism," purges, false accusations, insincere self-criticisms, arrests, executions, books disappearing overnight from bookshops and library shelves, names becoming unmentionable, photographs being doctored, NKVD requisitioning of archives, blatant lying. The days of such massive purges, arrests and executions may be over, the days of NKVD destruction of archives may be over, but the legacy of which these were a part is with us still. There is still much evasion and deceit. Casting its shadow over the academic life of the socialist countries and the intellectual life of some of the communist parties, there is the official history of Marxism, shallow, schematic, triumphalist, full of semiceremonial phrases, empty jargon, hollow self-praise. Below it, the real history of Marxism, in so far as it is known, leads a subterranean existence. Names, unmentioned in public, are whispered in quiet places. The story can be told in bits and pieces, but it cannot be published.

Such books as Roy Medvedev's Let History Judge (London, 1976) and his brother Zhores Medvedev's The Rise and Fall of T.D. Lysenko (NY, 1969) have come as a breath of fresh air, given prevailing conditions, in that they have spoken loudly of much that is only supposed to be whispered and have faced the difficult personal consequences of doing so. Although admirable books in many respects, they do not escape the assumptions of the second category, putting an exaggerated emphasis on the personality of Stalin and failing to give due attention to other operative factors.

As to the fourth category, the Althusserian trend is very ambiguous about the nature or the value of history, in so far as it recognizes it exists. Upon unraveling a complex historical argument, I was once answered by an Althusserian: "There is no such thing as history; there are only books on shelves." At the time it left me speechless, though I must admit that all the arguments I thought of on my way home to justify whatl had thought needed no justification deepened my sense of historicity. Even analytic philosophers, whom I had long since judged shockingly lacking in a sense of historicity, at least (if pressed), will admit that history exists and might even be nice to know (however inessential to philosophy in their sense of the term). As to Louis Althusser himself, he cannot outline the history of Marxist philosophy, because of a "symptomatic difficulty," for philosophy has no history:

Ultimately, philosophy has no history. Philosophy is that strange theoretical site where nothing really happens, nothing but this repetition of nothing. To say that nothing happens in philosophy is to say that philosophy leads nowhere because it is going nowhere. 6

He does admit that there is a history of the sciences and that the lines of the philosophical front are displaced according to the transformations of the scientific conjuncture, but this is "a history of the displacement of the indefinite repetition of a null trace whose effects are real." It is a trend of wide influence today, with Barry Hindness and Paul Hirst starkly declaring:

Marxism, as a theoretical and political practice, gains nothing from its association with historical writing and historical research. The study of history is not only scientifically but also politically valueless. 8

And this, may I remark, in a book about precapitalist modes of production. My advice to anyone wanting to know about precapitalist modes of production or the history of Marxist philosophy or anything else for that matter is to look elsewhere. What attempts have been made by Althusserians to look at what the normal run of the species considers to be historical matters have, not surprisingly, been singularly unilluminating. An example bearing on the problematic of this book is Althusser’s treatment of the debates in pre­ revolutionary Russian Marxism in Lenin and Philosophy (London, 1971). Unfortunately, the history of Marxism is as little known by today’s Marxists as by non-Marxists, with one Marxist recently finding it necessary to make the point that pre-1960s Marxism was no "pre-Althusserian dark age." 9 

As to my own approach to the historiography of Marxism, I have already revealed much and my chapters reveal more, but let me state clearly with regard to the interpretative categories set out above that:

1. While I feel I can trace a certain mainstream flow of the Marxist tradition, I find it to be far from an unproblematic straight line and I believe the various currents diverging from it must be analyzed respectfully and seriously as highlighting very real problems. (Parenthetically, let me explain that I have used the word Marxist in a fairly liberal sense, at least on the historiographical level, including virtually everyone who called themselves Marxist and situated their problematic within the Marxist tradition. I have, however, on the philosophical level, tried to show the inconsistencies of many such positions and the discontinuity of certain of their premises with certain features essential to Marxism as a distinctive intellectual tradition.) Moreover, I have defied the existing conventions, mentioned the unmentionable names, delved into delicate and difficult matters that others believed should be let lie. I have done so regretfully, even sorrowfully, for I could take no joy in the self-inflicted tragedies of the communist movement, as do anticommunist writers who are, for the most part, the only ones who write about such things. But, shaken though I sometimes found myself, I could not turn the other way, for I disagree totally with the premises underlying the tradition of sacrificing truth to "partisanship," in the name of which so many crimes against science and against humanity have been committed. The only justification for socialism can lie in arguing for its truth and its humanism. If so, truth, morality, and partisanship should coincide. Indeed, there have been truthful and moral communists, such as Gramsci and Caudwell, and no less partisan (in fact more so) for that.

2. I do not think this history would be an unproblematic straight line but for Stalin. While I admit his shadow looms very large over it and I have tried to assess his role in it, he was after all only one man and there was much happening. 

3. I take exception to the tendency to draw a sharp line between Marx, Lukacs, Korsch, and Gramsci on the one side, representing "creative" Marxism, and Engels, Lenin, Stalin, and a mostly nameless coterie as embodying "dogmatic" Marxism on the other. I have argued against the tenuous interpretations of Marx and the caricatures of Engels and Lenin upon which this trend is based. I have dealt respectfully, but critically, with Marx, Engels, and Lenin, and I have tried to set the assessment of their philosophical contribution upon a firmer basis. As far as subsequent Marxist thinkers are concerned, I think that good and not-so-good philosophers can be found on both sides of this arbitrary divide. To look at the Comintern period, for example, there can be no doubt that Gramsci towers over Stalin and Mitin. However, it is also my opinion that Caudwell towers over Korsch, yet there is a great fuss made over Korsch while Caudwell is forgotten. Korsch’s political dissent, more than the philosophical merit of his writings, is, in my opinion, responsible for his greater prominence than Caudwell's, who died as a Communist Party member. (There are other factors, I admit. After all, Gramsci too died a Communist Party member. Other factors also require analysis, such as why Italian Marxism has made far more of its own history than British Marxism.)

4. To the Althusserians, I must confess to being an unrepentant historicist. (I realize this term is a slippery one, with a wide range of usage. I use it to designate thinking pervaded by a deep sense of temporal process, which insists upon the value of genetic, historical, and causal explanation, though not in opposition to structural, logical, or systemic explanation. So specified, it is a way of thinking antithetical to the Althusserian way, although it is not Althusser’s own rather eccentric use of the term.) My argument is quite simply that we cannot separate human thought from the movement, the flow, the context of human thinking without thoroughly distorting what it actually is. The unfolding of history has formed us as what we are and shaped our modes of thought and there is no understanding any of it without a sense of the process that has brought it into being.

5. Far from believing Marxism to be the illusion of the epoch, I believe that, however problematic it has become and whatever criticisms may legitimately be laid at its door, there is still a point to Sartre’s statement that it remains the unsurpassed philosophy of our time. 10 Even if it be surpassed, and I am prepared to think that it may be, we shall still owe it much. For the time being, such features as its comprehensiveness, its coherence, and its orientation towards science still recommend it beyond any of its contenders so far.

It is my view that the history of Marxism needs to be seen as a complex and intricate story of persons, ideas, and events; as a process in which philosophical ideas have emerged and contended with one another in a complex and multifaceted interaction with the social, political, economic, and scientific forces at work at any given time. It needs to be viewed with a sensitivity to the passionate striving, to the astute analyses, to the intelligent and enduringly valid syntheses it has brought forth and, at the same time, with a willingness to look full in the face upon the dark side of it and to realize how and why it is that those who love wisdom need to walk warily, even among those who are supposedly of their own kind.

Regretfully, I am hard put to cite examples of work in the history of Marxist philosophy that meet these criteria — works that are comprehensive and sweeping, striving to bring into play the full network of interconnections, alert to the overall patterns of development, yet without sacrificing concreteness, thoroughness of research, or rigor of analysis; works that are sympathetic but critical. This, at any rate, is the challenge I have set for myself. It is for others to judge the extent to which I have met it. No doubt, I have fallen far short of what could have been done, given the complexity of the problematic with the immense possibilities it opens up and given the fact that it is nearly uncharted territory.

Not altogether uncharted, however. Although there is no overall history of Marxist philosophy of science, there are some rather good histories of certain episodes of it. The only area in which major works are already in existence, however, is in the history of Soviet philosophy of science, the most notable works being David Joravsky's Soviet Marxism and Natural Science (London, 1961), which covers the period from 1917 to 1932, and The Lysenko Affair (Cambridge, Mass., 1970); and Loren Graham's Science and Philosophy in the Soviet Union (New York, 1973) the weight of which is on the postwar period, but which nevertheless contains much valuable material on the prewar period. These works are invaluable sources, adhering to the highest standards of scholarship, and I have not hesitated to draw upon them in my fourth chapter. However, even in the field of Soviet philosophy of science, where such significant work has already been done, there are gaps to be filled and interpretative issues to be clarified. I believe that many of the facts and ideas set out by Joravsky should be seen in a somewhat different light. While basically I agree with Graham, I prefer to give greater weight to the political context in dealing with philosophy of science than he does.

Regarding my other chapters, there are no such major parallel works. However, there are, in every case, in addition to the primary sources, a variety of types of secondary sources that touch on certain aspects of the chapter. About the work of certain authors, there is a voluminous body of secondary literature, but little or nothing about others. I have undertaken to review this secondary literature where it exists and to take a specific interpretative position. In cases of an extensive body of literature, where an exhaustive survey would be impossible, I have attempted to select in a representative manner, so as to indicate the overall range of interpretative patterns. In matters of ongoing controversy, such as that of the Marx-Engels relationship and that of the relationship of the Oparin-Haldane hypothesis to Marxist philosophy, I have weighed the evidence and argued a very definite position.

In every chapter, my general method has been to sketch the relevant historical background, to outline the terms of the philosophical debates, to show their connections to other debates, to evaluate the various philosophical arguments put forward, to determine their significance within the history of Marxist philosophy of science as a whole, and to review critically the secondary literature. But that is only the roughest and most superficial characterization of the book's method. Working through it in detail and in depth has forced me to wrestle with a host of exceedingly intricate and thorny methodological issues.

Perhaps the most important of these underlying issues concerns the relationship between the philosophical and the historical dimensions of this work. This is not an easy matter to discuss. It would be difficult enough if I only had to explain myself to those who believe as I do in the historicity of philosophy, and I mean a deep, internal, and constitutive historicity, rooted in the historicity of rationality itself. To those who know, and know deeply, why the history of the philosophy of science is essential to the philosophy of science, I would have problem enough defending what I have done and how I have done it. However, living as I do in a world full of analytic philosophers and Althusserians, nothing can be taken for granted, and if I wish to defend my method, my task is far more complicated. I fear, however, that I may be talking across insuperable barriers in trying to explain myself to those to whom the slightest hint of historical scholarship automatically lays one open to the charge of being "insufficiently philosophical" or to those for whom a "symptomatic difficulty" already declares the end result to be a nullity.

Most philosophers today are utterly oblivious of the fact that philosophy or science is historical, except in the most trivial and superficial sense. Even when they do look at the history of philosophy or science they do so in such a thoroughly ahistorical and noncontextual way, that anybody could virtually have said anything at any time. In philosophy, the ideas of Plato, Aristotle, Descartes, Hume, Kant, Hegel, Carnap, and Quine are treated as discrete and interchangeable units, virtually independent of time and place, and generated in an autonomous activity with no necessary or integral connection to anything else. If temporal sequence or economic, social, political, or scientific developments are mentioned, it is only in an accidental or circumstantial way. It is exceedingly rare today to find a philosoher with a real sense of the flow, the movement, the process of the history of philosophy or science and with a vivid sense of its integral connection with economics, culture, politics, and science.

This being so, the whole debate over the relationship of the philosophy of science to the history of science among philosophers of science has been an extremely constructive one, though its inadequacies are painfully apparent in the strained attempts to set up awkward interactions between an ahistorical philosophy of science and a nonphilosophical history of science. Even while making a stab at overcoming this syndrome, Kuhn declares:

Subversion is not, I think, too strong a term for the likely result of an attempt to make the two fields into one. ... The final product of most historical research is a narrative, a story, about particulars of the past. ... The philosopher, on the other hand, aims principally at explicit generalizations and at those with universal scope. He is no teller of stories, true or false. His goal is to discover and state what is true at all times and places rather than to impart understanding of what occurred at a particular time and place. 11

The contrast is falsely drawn and the subversion he fears would be, in my opinion, no bad thing. I see no reason why the philosopher should not be a teller of stories and be fully a philosopher in doing so. Certainly coming to terms with the history of philosophy and the history of science is no diversion from being a philosopher and writing such history is a thoroughly philosophical task.

Actually, there is far greater philosophical rigor called into play in the real struggle to make sense of the turbulent complexity of the world of historical experience than in shallow formal schemes of the hothouse world in which the analytic philosophers build their careers. At any rate, in the practical task of writing this history, I felt fully a philosopher in doing so. So many times I found that historiographical problems came down to epistemological problems, which in turn came down to ontological ones. While on the surface of it, I sometimes experienced a tension between narrative and thematic considerations and I often found the task of keeping the thread of the story going, while doing full justice to the theoretical issues involved, a bit tricky to organize, it was a creative tension. On a deeper level, as I tried both to tell the story and to assess its philosophical significance, two tasks that I found to be thoroughly intertwined at every step along the way, I came to realize more fully just how deep and multifaceted are the interconnections between considerations involved in giving a historical account and those involved in putting forward a philosophical analysis. Lukács once expressed one dimension of this quite starkly:

Without a Weltanschauung, it is impossible to narrate properly or to achieve a composition which would reflect the differentiated and especially complete variety of life. 12

It is true. In any case, it is quite clear to me that my own world view has in deep, complex and decisive ways shaped my telling of this story. I acknowledge this straight out. Although I have tried to be fair even in relation to positions with which I disagree, I have been no detached observer. Although I have not used the first person in my chapters, except in footnotes, or given an explicit declaration de foi at every turn, I have nevertheless made my position, which in many ways cuts across the lines of historical debate, plain. Because I believe my philosophical assumptions to be justified, I believe this has enhanced my historical account. Those who do not share my assumptions will not think so. So be it, for it cannot be otherwise. Nevertheless, those who share my assumptions will inevitably see ways I could have fulfilled my task better and hopefully those who do not will not find me too wanting in standards of scholarship and argumentation.

It is, of course, one thing to analyze the integral connection of philosophy to history and context, and another to implement such an analysis in terms of philosophical and historiographical technique. Within my own terms of reference, this has meant a constant alertness, not only to all the forms of interaction in the shifting nexus of science, philosophy, and politics, but to all the levels of interaction within each of these forms. It has meant the need to show in each period and set of circumstances the effects of science on philosophy, of philosophy on science, of science and philosophy on politics, of politics on science and philosophy. But within each of these categories, there are many levels of effects.

For example, as to the effects of politics on philosophy of science:

There is first of all the most obvious level — the effect of overt political events on the fate of individual philosophers and scientists. Thus, the tradition was deprived of any further work on the part of Guest or Caudwell when they died fighting in the Spanish Civil War, of Politzer or Solomon when they were executed by the Gestapo, of Gramsci when he died in prison, of Hessen or Uranovsky or Vavilov when they were swept up in the purges.

On a slightly different level, a bit more complicated to assess, there are the effects of political transformations on the development of the disciplines of philosophy and science and the relations between them. Thus, the October Revolution opened to Marxism the resources of institutional power, bringing into the discussion of philosophy of science a great vigor and enormous scale that was highly valued as integral to the task of building a new social order, and then crushing it through shortcircuiting rational procedures with clumsy or vicious attempts to settle philosophical and scientific questions by administrative measures. There are many factors to be taken into account to comprehend the shift in Soviet intellectual life as the 1920s passed into the 1930s, such as the impact of the inauguration of the first Five Year Plan upon the changeover from bourgeois to "red" specialists, the function of the concept of "proletarian science,” with many new complications arising; but it was even then a society which at one and the same time put an unprecedentedly high social value upon philosophy of science, even while they brought to bear the dark and destructive forces that would overpower it. Also, roughly on the same level, are the various shifts in the whole style of the intellectual life of the communist movement corresponding to the various shifts in Comintern policy, especially the shift from the sectarian third-period war on "social fascism" to the more expansive period of the Popular Front.

There are many further levels, with the various primary and secondary sources drawing all sorts of connecting links between political factors and philosophical and scientific ones, sometimes quite to the point and sometimes far from it, but all of them showing the truth of Haldane’s discovery that, while the professors may leave politics alone, politics will not leave the professors alone.

Finally at the deepest level, there comes the problem of discerning just how the prevailing political milieu enters into the philosophical thought process itself and into the scientific thought process itself. Politics, itself rooted in and connected to economics in exceedingly intricate ways, mediates in the formation of ideologies that bind fundamental assumptions to class interests in exceedingly intricate (and hidden) ways. (I use the term ideology to indicate a system of interrelated attitudes, based on a specific system of values and ties to the interests of a specific social force. I am aware of the fact that Marxists are split on the use of the term ideology and I believe the more general, nonpejorative sense of the term is preferable to the one that associates it with false consciousness.) I do not believe that intellectual history follows upon the development of economic and political factors in simple and uncomplicated ways. The connections can be of an extraordinarily complex and subtle nature, with all sorts of complications arising from overlapping and countervailing tendencies. It is an area beset with difficulties, for it has been so littered with facile and even malicious tendencies to assert direct and simple one-to-one correspondences between ideas and classes. The left’s habit of writing off people and premises as "bourgeois" or "petty bourgeois" has all too often provided a refuge for those who have had neither arguments nor conscience against those who have and it has not been grounded in a proper understanding of the real class basis of patterns of thinking. It is an area in which it is necessary to proceed with caution, but at the same time it is an area that must not be avoided.

At all events, I have tried to be sensitive to all the interconnections I could discover, both overt and subtle, both direct and indirect, both immediate and epochal. I have probed to uncover the relationship of various thought patterns to various class forces and to various stages of development. I have tried to understand what it is about the mode of existence of the bourgeoisie as a class that ties the social order under its hegemony to patterns of thought that swing between reductionism, dualism, and idealism. I have also tried to understand what it is about identifying with the cause of the proletariat that puts the stress on totality and makes materialism seem most appropriate philosophy. Marxism itself embodies its own explanation of this, being not only an integrated world view, but a critique of a social order that structurally inhibits the formation of an integrated world view and a theory of a new social order that is the necessary social matrix for an integrated world view. It renounces any disjunction of philosophy and politics as symptomatic of the intellectual fragmentation endemic to the capitalist mode of production and holds that the integration of all spheres can be achieved only in a new consciousness tied to a new mode of production.

This being the case, no history of Marxist philosophy of science could be anything but superficial if it could not give some account of the historical convergence between the critique of dualism, reductionism, and idealism on the one hand and the critique of capitalism on the other, between a tradition striving to set out an integrated world view and a movement towards a classless society. The Marxist argument that the historical convergence is grounded in an integral and logical connection is a forceful and fascinating one. But the logic can only manifest itself historically and the argument can only be filled out in and through the telling of the story.

Notes

1. Marx Wartofsky, “Politics, Political Philosophy and the Politics of Philosophy,” in Revolutions, Systems and Theories, ed. H.J. Johnson, J.J. Leach, and R.G. Muehlmann (Dordrecht, 1979), p. 144.

2. The older Lukacs used this phrase in objecting to the tendency to take his own early work and that of others as offering the solution to the present-day problems of Marxism. Cf. the interview with Lukacs in New Left Review, no. 68 (July-August 1971), pp. 55–56.

3. The term is given a special meaning by Althusser and his followers. Cf. Althusser and Balibar, Reading Capital (London, 1970).

4. H.B. Acton, The Illusion of the Epoch (London, 1972). (Originally published, 1949)

5. Marx Wartofsky, “The Unhappy Consciousness,” Praxis International (October 1981): p. 291.

6. Louis Althusser, Lenin and Philosophy (London, 1971), p. 56.

7. Ibid., pp. 62-63.

8. B. Hindness and P. Hirst, Pre-Capitalist Modes of Production (London, 1975), p. 312.

9. Robert Gray, Review of Rebels and Their Causes: Essays in Honour of A.L. Morton, ed. Maurice Cornforth, in Comment, 23 June 1979.

10. Jean-Paul Sartre, Search for a Method (New York, 1968), p. 30.

11. Thomas Kuhn, The Essential Tension (Chicago, 1977), p. 5.

12. György Lukács, Marxism and Human Liberation (New York, 1973), p. 126.

Book Review: Marxism and the Philosophy of Science

ByGeorge Martin Fell Brown
SOCIALIST ALTERNATIVE
August 1, 2019


Marxists are primarily known for their concern with the development of human society and political struggle. As materialists, however, Marxists necessarily look to developments in science and new ways of understanding the material world. The Marxist interest in science entails both a search for a scientific understanding of the material forces that shape society, as well as the ways social forces shape our scientific understanding itself. Under capitalism, however, the Marxist interest in science hasn’t been accompanied by an embrace of Marxism by scientists. Capitalism portrays science as a purely objective phenomenon and considers any attempt at understanding the political implications of science to be an intrusion of ideology into the sphere of objective, scientific neutrality.

This distrustful attitude of scientists towards Marxism has been exacerbated by the legacy of Stalinism. In addition to waging a campaign of bureaucratic counter-revolutionary terror, Stalinism cracked down on significant scientific developments, dismissing genetics, modern physics, and important breakthroughs in psychology, while promoting pseudo-scientific ideas like Lysenkoism. All of this was done in the name of Marxism, which made it all the easier for capitalists to hold it up as a warning of the danger of letting politics interfere with science. Through this the forces of both Stalinism and capitalism served to bury a vibrant legacy of genuine Marxist thought concerning questions of science and the philosophy of science.

With this in mind, the recent republication of Helena Sheehan’s Marxism and the Philosophy of Science can only be welcomed. Originally written in 1985, but reprinted at the end of 2017, Sheehan’s book recounts a wide history of serious Marxist thought on science starting with Marx and Engels themselves, and going up to the mass workers’ movements of the 1930s and 1940s. In keeping with a dialectical conception of science, Marxist ideas aren’t presented as static but evolving through debate and experiment in the face of new scientific and political challenges. This is a history of revolutionaries grappling with the scientific revolutions of their day, of a flourishing of scientific development in post-revolutionary Russia, of the strangling of that development under Stalinist degeneration, and of a new wave of politicized scientists in the west coming to terms with the political implications of their work.

Sheehan reveals the philosophical outlook of Marxism, often termed “dialectical materialism” to be infinitely more vibrant than the Stalinist caricature that persists in the popular imagination. More importantly she reveals it to be far more vibrant than the views on science that dominate the capitalist world. Western, non-Marxist philosophy of science, has created its own historical lineage of figures like Mach, Carnap, Popper, Kuhn, Lakatos, and Feyerabend. This lineage often featured philosophers dramatically overturning the over-simplistic conceptions of their predecessors, only to replace them with new over-simplistic conceptions of their own. As Sheehan points out “The trajectory of this tradition, from positivism to the current variety of postpositivist philosophies of science, has reflected the pressure of a complex reality upon conceptions too restricted to give an adequate account of it.”

The Marxist tradition, Sheehan points out, provides an alternate view of the history of science. Responding to the same “pressure of a complex reality” the Marxist dialectical approach proved much more resilient, as we’ll examine later.

When this book was first published in 1985, neoliberalism was in the midst of an ideological counter-revolution against socialist and Marxist ideas. But in the field of science, there was still a minority, including figures like Richard Lewontin and Richard Levins as well as the Science for the People movement, who kept fighting the good fight.

The republication of the book comes in a very different time period, one of rising support for socialist ideas, as well as rising discussion around the relation of science and politics. Donald Trump’s attacks on climate science provoked the March for Science, the largest demonstration of scientists in world history. Meanwhile political conflict has flared up within the scientific community as ideas of “race science” have made a comeback among on the far right. In this situation, a better understanding of Marxist views on science, as presented in this book, can be a valuable tool.
Marx, Engels, and Dialectical Materialism

The Marxist conception of philosophy of science began, of course, with Marx and Engels themselves. Sheehan puts these ideas in the context of the nineteenth-century thought they came out of. The previous century saw the enlightenment promise to do away with religious and idealist ideas once and for all with a thorough-going materialist worldview. “Idealism,” in the philosophical sense, refers to the approach that sees ideas or the spirit as the basis of reality, while “materialism” sees the natural universe as the basis. By the nineteenth century, materialism had run into hurdles, seeing a resurgence of idealist thought in the form of Hegel, who challenged the rigid, mechanical formulations of the enlightenment ideas. Marx and Engels came out of the Young Hegelian movement, which tried to more extensively engage in political struggle. And engaging in these struggles brought Marx and Engels back to materialism, but of a different kind than during the enlightenment.

As Marx and Engels threw themselves into the political struggles and revolutions of the mid-nineteenth century they sought, more than any of their political contemporaries, to understand the real-life social forces shaping those political struggles. They looked to the process of labor, the conscious human interaction with nature, and the relations of production, as the basis of those forces. Wider political and ideological questions couldn’t be separated from this interaction but rather had to be seen in terms of the labor and class relations in society. And changing society required understanding the way those classes come into conflict and how social relations break down and transform. This necessitated a materialist worldview applied to questions of history and politics, which had been absent in their Young Hegelian milieu.

Materialist ideas in science predate Marx and Engels by quite a bit, with forms of materialism going as far back as ancient Greece and being a significant part of the philosophy of the enlightenment in the eighteenth century. But the application of materialist methods for understanding the internal workings of society was a revolutionary contribution in more ways than one. Not only did it point to direct social and political revolution, it pointed to a different understanding of materialism itself. The materialism of the enlightenment philosophers was a highly mechanical conception, reducing nature and society to fixed objects either existing in stasis or confined to simple motion. The materialist conception of history put forward by Marx and Engels didn’t adhere to that approach.

This is where Marx and Engels brought in the dialectical ideas from their Young Hegelian upbringing. A dialectical approach to the universe saw objects, ideas, and other categories as dynamic and fluid. Things couldn’t be reduced to fixed categories, but had to be seen as a complex of contradictory processes, coming into being, impacting each other, and becoming transformed into other categories. This was Hegel’s approach, but Hegel saw these contradictions and transformations as taking place only within the world of ideas. From Marx and Engels’ materialist perspective, these contradictions and transformations are part of nature itself.

In the world of science, new discoveries were taking place that increasingly confirmed Marx and Engels’ dialectical worldview and calling into question the mechanical approach put forward by previous materialists. The discovery of geological time early in the nineteenth century, and the discovery of biological evolution in the middle of the century revealed the dialectical character of nature itself. If the Hegelians responded to these developments by eschewing materialism, many of the scientific thinkers of the time attempted to address the question through increased reductionism or increased fracturing of science into different specialties. Marx and Engels paid close attention to new scientific developments and, as scientific questions increasingly collided with political questions, Engels directly brought up this dialectical conception of nature.

Sheehan discusses three key works of Engels on the question: Anti-Dühring, The Dialectics of Nature, and Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Classical German Philosophy. The first of these was a polemic against Eugen Dühring, a briefly popular figure in the socialist movement, who put forward a crudely mechanical and schematic approach to science and politics. The Dialectics of Nature was an unfinished work, inspired by Marx’s own desire to write a work salvaging what was rational in Hegel’s thought. And Ludwig Feuerbach was a historical account of the philosophical road leading from Hegel to Marx.

In these works Engels grappled with a number of scientific questions of his day, from a dialectical perspective. He pointed to a number of the laws of development Hegel had put forward, such as the transformation of quantity into quality, and pointed out how they arise in nature and not simply in thought, as Hegel had put forward. He looked into how social conditions shaped scientific discovery.

In addressing developments like Darwin’s ideas of evolution and natural selection, he made some contributions of his own, pointing to the role of labor in the evolution of consciousness. These ideas served both to challenge some of the crude “social Darwinist” ideas – which stated that capitalism and imperialism were a “natural” state of affairs, embodying the “struggle of the fittest” – while still defending the legitimacy of Darwinism against neo-Lamarckian ideas espoused by figures on the left like Dühring. Jean-Baptiste Lamarck was an advocate of evolution predating Darwin who advocated the inheritance of acquired characteristics, rather than natural selection, as the basis for evolution. Dühring identified natural selection with “social Darwinist” ideas and turned back to Lamarck’s ideas on moral grounds. Ironically, when Stalin waged his war on genetics, he was actually putting forward the very neo-Lamarckian ideas Engels polemicized against.

Sheehan contrasts Engels favorably with a number of other philosophers of science who have more respectability in the bourgeois media. Many ideas attributed to twentieth century philosophers were formulated earlier by Engels and with much more nuance. This is seen in Engels’s critique of “positivism.” “Positivism” refers to the rejection of philosophy in favor of adopting an (often oversimplified) understanding of natural science as the basis for all theoretical and practical activity. The critique of the simplistic positivistic conception of scientific discovery, with its crude emphasis on induction, is often attributed to the reactionary “Cold-War Warrior” Karl Popper. But Engels already raised such criticisms long before Popper, and Popper only replaced one simplistic conception with another. Meanwhile, Engels put forward ideas of scientific revolutions and crises that are often attributed to Popper’s opponent, Thomas Kuhn. But Engels brought in a wider social dynamic behind his conception of scientific revolutions that Kuhn didn’t employ.

Sheehan also deals with some controversies that have developed in academic Marxist circles around the relation of Marx to Engels. Various academic trends, either adhering to a crude materialism or a rejection of materialism, have tried to attribute dialectical materialist ideas exclusively to Engels. Either Marx was a positivist and Engels smuggled in dialectics, or Marx was a Hegelian idealist and Engels smuggled in materialism. Since Marx’s published writings didn’t deal as extensively with science as Engels’, this allowed some leeway for these interpretations. But Sheehan clearly shows these ideas are unfounded, pointing to numerous instances of Marx explicitly defending materialist and dialectical conceptions of science.

Since Sheehan’s book was first published in 1985, even further evidence has come out challenging these academic Marxist misconceptions. Previously unpublished scientific notebooks of Marx’s have been re-discovered, with extensive attention given to questions of ecology and agricultural science. More recent writings by John Bellamy Foster, Paul Burkett, and Kohei Saito have revealed new dimensions of a dialectical approach to science in these writings. In addition, more is known about the role of Carl Schorlemmer, the “red chemist,” an organic chemist and Fellow of the Royal Society who collaborated closely with Marx and Engels and actively embraced a dialectical approach to science.

Given that new research, it’s unfortunate that it doesn’t appear in Sheehan’s book. One can imagine that if it had been written today, Sheehan would have a lot more to say on the topic.
The “Crises” in Marxism and Physics

As a worldview, Marxism was the product of clashes with other political trends on the left, from anarchism to utopian socialism to Blanquist putschism, and of ideological clashes with bourgeois economists and scientists. This is in contrast to more undialectical ideologies, which try to derive their worldview from first principles. Following Marx and Engels’ deaths, Marxism wasn’t just the thought of one or two individuals, but of a whole movement, organized in the Second International, modeled off of the International Workingman’s Association of the time of Marx and Engels.

The late 19th and early 20th century saw a prolonged period of stability for capitalism that provoked what was deemed a “crisis in Marxism.” A trend around Eduard Bernstein sought to ditch Marx’s revolutionary politics in favor of bringing about change solely through reforms. This debate took on a philosophical component as the reformists also relied on a neo-Kantian revival in popular philosophy. Meanwhile, another wing of the movement, centering around Alexander Bogdanov in Russia and Anton Pannekoek in the Netherlands, defended revolutionary politics from a crude, ultra-left, voluntaristic perspective, and appealed to a new wave of positivist philosophy around the physicist Ernst Mach.

The wider development of the neo-Kantian and Machian schools was less motivated by the “crisis in Marxism” and more by a concurrent “crisis in physics.” The Newtonian revolution in physics had exhausted itself, and new discoveries were poking holes in its foundations. The neo-Kantian movement reflected an increasing distrust in science and especially the possibility of scientific progress. Machism was an attempt at defending science by clearing away the problems of previous schools of positivism. Mach tried to build a “second wave of positivism” which downplayed the original positivists’ focus on scientific laws and objects in favor of the methods and processes of science. As with many undialectical approaches to science, it was able to point to legitimate problems with previous undialectical conceptions, only to replace them with new problems.

In the year 1905, two revolutionary events occurred. In Russia, the workers rose up against tsarism, setting up soviets, or workers’ councils, posing the possibility of overthrowing capitalism for the first time since the Paris Commune. The uprising was defeated, but it would prove to be a “dress rehearsal” preparing the Russian masses for the successful revolution of 1917. At the same time, Albert Einstein began a revolution in physics with his discovery of the theories of special and general relativity. These developments pointed the way to resolving both the “crisis in Marxism” and the “crisis in physics.” But it would take time.

Sheehan goes over the various debates within the Second International and comes out with a critical view of many of the leaders of the International for their failure to adequately address the scientific questions. To varying degrees, most of the leading theoreticians of the International, from Karl Kautsky to Paul Lafargue to the Austro-Marxists, sought to reduce the scope of Marxism, either to just economics, or just history. Questions of science and philosophy were treated as private matters. So while Kautsky critiqued Bernstein for his political positions, he argued that Bernstein’s philosophical views were still compatible with Marxism.

Not all of the thinkers of the Second International held that view. Joseph Dietzgen and Antonio Labriola took a more serious approach to philosophy. Most importantly, Georgi Plekhanov, the father of Russian Marxism, took the philosophical questions very seriously, and he and the resulting Russian Marxist movement would make the most thorough-going critiques of these new philosophical trends.

In their own ways, neo-Kantianism and Machism posed a challenge to materialism primarily on the plane of epistemology: the branch of philosophy dealing with knowledge. A materialist conception would hold that our knowledge of the outside world in some way reflects or corresponds to material reality. The seeming “crisis in physics” revealed that a lot of previously accepted knowledge of physics didn’t correspond to reality. But the solutions posed by neo-Kantianism and Machism only added new problems.

The neo-Kantians argued that there was a rigid separation between the phenomenon, the thing as it appears, and the noumenon, the thing in itself. With this rigid separation between perception and reality, the discovery of truth was confined to “pure reason” and universal principles disconnected from experience. The scientific understanding of society was rejected and socialism, if defended at all, had to be seen as a “moral imperative.”

The Machians took the opposite approach to the neo-Kantians. They saw perception and reality as identical and dismissed as metaphysics the very idea of any form of reality existing beyond the realm of perception. When scientists were first coming to terms with the limitations of Newtonian mechanics, Mach’s ideas held a certain appeal. But the more relativity and quantum physics were formalized and standardized, the less use Machism had, and this sort of subjective idealism has increasingly been associated with anti-scientific philosophies like postmodernism.

Sheehan points out that Plekhanov, and many other leaders of the Russian Marxist movement, took thorough philosophical aim at these ideas. But they generally avoided taking this philosophical debate into the “crisis in physics” itself. The main exception to this was Lenin, in his 1909 book Materialism and Empirio-Criticism. This was a response to the Machian ideas of Bogdanov, who was playing an ultra-left role within Lenin’s Bolshevik faction of the Russian Social Democratic and Labor Party. Bogdanov had failed to come to terms with the defeat of the 1905 revolution and was increasingly pushing for adventuristic tactics to will the revolution back into existence, backing this up with appeals to Mach’s ideas. Even though Lenin wasn’t a scientist, he was forced to take up the debates in the scientific community as they had spilled over into politics.

Materialism and Empirio-Criticism argues that, in contrast to the claims of Mach, material reality does, in fact, exist outside of direct perception. The problem wasn’t with materialist epistemology, but with an undialectical, metaphysical materialism, that conflated an era’s conception of reality with reality in general. Due to the nature of dialectics, material reality was in flux, and our ideas of reality were only partial reflections. This open-ended conception meant new discoveries would be made that would require updating our understanding of how material reality operated, but didn’t negate the existence of objective reality or our ability to understand it.

There are many limitations of Materialism and Empirio-Criticism and it remains a deeper cut of Lenin’s oeuvre. The revolution in physics was only in the process of being completed, and the book still references things like the luminiferous ether, which was thrown out by the development of relativity theory, but was still being included in the textbooks of the time. Meanwhile quantum physics wouldn’t be formalized until after Lenin’s death, so it’s not dealt with in Materialism and Empirio-Criticism at all. Lenin also makes some unnecessary concessions to the positivists he’s debating with, for instance overstating the role of passive perception in obtaining knowledge at the expense of more active experience. But it is has stood the test of time much more so than the neo-Kantian and Machist ideas he was challenged with.

After Stalin came to power in the Soviet Union, many of the ideas Lenin put forward in Materialism and Empirio-Criticism would be distorted beyond recognition. Lenin was fundamentally defending the new scientific ideas while challenging the bad philosophical views that had accompanied them. Stalin, on the other hand, conflated the scientific ideas with the philosophical ideas, and insisted that relativity and quantum physics themselves were bourgeois perversions. Cold War anti-Communists tended to take Stalin at his word when he claimed to be espousing Lenin’s views, and this was used to levy a number of unfounded attacks on Materialism and Empirio-Criticism. Lenin’s real contribution was buried under these twin distortions. And it wasn’t the only Marxist contribution to science to be buried by Stalinism and Cold War anti-Communism.
Science After October

In contrast to the reputation set by Stalin, the immediate aftermath of the Russian Revolution saw a widening of discussion and debate on scientific and philosophical thought. The Bolsheviks made conscious efforts to win scientists to the revolution. While Lenin and Trotsky rejected many of the bourgeois caricatures of science, they likewise rejected the idea that revolutionaries could simply conjure up their own “proletarian science.” Dialectical materialism presupposes an open-ended conception of science, and Lenin and Trotsky specifically looked to “militant materialist” natural scientists, whether Marxist or not, to develop a more thorough-going dialectical materialism.

The Bolshevik government set up a number of scientific institutions and journals. And they consciously cultivated a wide freedom of discussion on scientific and philosophical matters. Many of the Machians who Lenin had harshly polemicized against were given prominent positions in the scientific institutions. And a wide variety of philosophical schools popped up, many at odds with Marxist views. Sheehan describes these schools, giving focus on the two most prominent: the mechanists and the Deborinites.

The mechanist school developed a wide following among natural scientists attracted to the Russian Revolution. Diverging wildly from a traditional Marxist conception, they adopted a strong positivist approach that saw the development of science as a replacement for all philosophy, including dialectical materialism. While among the most ultra-left figures in combating religious superstitions that remained in the Soviet Union, they tended to be more conservative when it came to the prejudices that existed within the scientific community itself.

Traditionally a “mechanical” or “mechanistic” approach is presented as the opposite of a dialectical approach. And in many ways, the mechanist school advocated the rigid fixed categories that Hegel and Marx had rebelled against. The Soviet mechanist school didn’t reject dialectics as wrong per se. Rather they saw scientific development as going in a more dialectical direction to the point where new understandings of the disturbance and re-establishment of equilibrium could subsume notions of dialectical contradiction. The mechanistic philosopher I.I. Skortsov-Stepanov argued that “the dialectical understanding of nature takes concrete form precisely as the mechanical understanding.” However many of these new scientific ideas would themselves become ossified and overturned in later scientific revolutions, and dialectics still remains necessary to understand the development of science.

The other major scientific school centered around the figure of Abram Deborin. Deborin was a Menshevik and a disciple of Plekhanov who broke with the Mensheviks to support the Russian Revolution. He was well-versed in Marxist philosophy and fully embraced a dialectical approach. But he drew more of his support from professional philosophers than natural scientists, and his school was often prone to less rigorous and more abstract arguments. The debate between the mechanists and Deborinites grew throughout the 1920s.

An important component of this debate concerned the relation of social and political transformation to science. The mechanists, while seeing science as playing a role in the material development of society, saw science itself as a neutral and objective study, unshaped by social change. The Deborinites had a clearer view of the way that different social systems shape scientific discovery. But they also saw science as exclusively part of the “ideological superstructure” in society. But science is a complicated process that can’t fit into one distinct role. The process of scientific research and discovery is shaped by both the “economic base” and the “ideological superstructure,” but science itself studies phenomena in nature that have their own laws, operating independently of both.

In spite of, or because of, these debates, Soviet science was able to see serious advancements that culminated in the impact of the Soviet delegation at the Second International Congress of the History of Science and Technology held in London in 1931. The delegation, headed by Nikolai Bukharin, brought thinkers from all sides in the debates, and made the case for the Marxist contribution to science. The conference had a profound effect on many radical British scientists in the 1930s. And the delegation’s documents, published under the title Science at the Crossroads, would provide inspiration for a later generation of radical scientists in the ‘60s and ‘70s. But much of the progress represented at this conference would be squelched under the bureaucratic counter-revolution already in progress.
Stalin’s Counter-Revolution in Science

As vibrant scientific debates were taking place throughout Soviet society, another, much less vibrant, “debate” was taking place in Soviet political life. The isolation of the Soviet Union lead to the consolidation of an increasingly parasitic bureaucracy centered around the figure of Joseph Stalin. After consolidating a bureaucratic counter-revolutionary dictatorship, Stalin proceeded to carry out a counter-revolution in the sphere of science. The Bolsheviks’ encouragement of scientific debate was put to an end. The bureaucracy now enshrined specific scientific principles, often of dubious merit. Defenders of legitimate scientific discoveries were thrown into gulags or executed. And all of this was done in the name of “Marxism.”

During the late 1920s, Stalin confined his purge to his immediate political opponents among the Bolsheviks, first lining up with Bukharin to crush Trotsky’s Left Opposition, and then turning his guns on Bukharin, who formed his own Right Opposition. However, it was still possible to carry on debate about scientific and philosophical questions, provided they were sufficiently detached from the main political disputes. But by the ‘30s, the counter-revolution had expanded to all spheres of Soviet political life, science included. The two wings of the scientific debates of the ‘20s were arbitrarily identified with different opposition groupings, with the mechanists being identified with Bukharin, and the Deborinites with Trotsky. Those opposition groupings were then falsely charged with being fascist agents as part of an increasingly wild official conspiracy theory.

Purges in the field of psychology put a premature halt to the pioneering work of Lev Vygotsky. In the field of physics, even though Lenin had explicitly defended the compatibility of relativity theory with dialectical materialism, the Stalinist bureaucracy insisted otherwise. And in biology, even though Engels expressly defended Darwinian natural selection against the neo-Lamarckianism of Dühring, the Stalinists propped up the neo-Lamarckian agronomist Trofim Lysenko as the face of Soviet Science.

Lysenko rejected the legitimacy of genetics and argued that inheritance of acquired characteristics could allow crops to be rapidly bred to grow in environments they weren’t suited for. The very science of genetics was denounced as bourgeois ideology. Biologists who opposed Lyenkoism, such as Israel Agol and Max Levin were arrested and shot under charges of Trotskyism. Lysenkoism continued into the ‘40s using more and more dubious scientific methods and claiming increasingly implausible results. During the Cold War, anti-Communists would point to the “Lysenko affair” in an attempt to dismiss Marxism as a whole.

The Stalinist bureaucracy, however, was prone to numerous zigzags, both political and philosophical. During World War II, the Soviet military relied on a serious approach to science, at least in certain fields. This forced the bureaucracy to eventually embrace the new physics, and most Soviet physicists were spared from the purges. And while Stalin put forward a caricature of dialectics in the ‘30s, the nationalist promotion of anti-German sentiments during the war led Stalin to downgrade dialectics altogether, holding up formal logic so that “Soviet men may learn to think effectively” while dismissing Hegel as a mere “aristocratic reaction to the French Revolution.”

Sheehan’s history only goes up to 1948, so it doesn’t cover what happened to Soviet science after then. In spite of Stalin’s political and scientific counter-revolution, Soviet science nonetheless made enormous contributions after World War II. A key event highlighting was the launching of Sputnik 1, the first artificial satellite, into orbit in 1957. This was a huge shock to U.S. imperialism which led to a massive investment in the race to get to the moon as well as more investment in science education generally.

The successes of Soviet science stemmed from the fact that, in spite of its bureaucratic degeneration, the Soviet Union maintained a planned economy. Science education and research was seen as a priority and received significant state support. The planned economy allowed Russia to rapidly develop from a mostly illiterate semi-feudal country under Tsarism, to a world leader in science and mathematics under the Soviet Union. However, this success was hampered by the lack of a dialectical materialist approach to science. This, and the lack of democracy within the planned economy, caused Soviet science to replicate some of the problems of capitalist science. This was most stark in the case of the environment. The Soviet bureaucracy’s refusal to consider the environmental impact of the forced pace of industrialization resulted in Chernobyl nuclear disaster and the ecosystem collapse of the Aral sea.

Sheehan does a good job at outlining the decline in scientific thought that took place under Stalin. But she falters when trying to understand how it happened. She suggests that, had Trotsky or Bukharin succeeded Lenin instead of Stalin, things would have turned out for the better. In her new afterword to the current edition of the book, she more explicitly aligns herself with Bukharin rather than Trotsky. While she correctly rejects the Stalinists’ false identification of Trotsky with Deborinism, she makes her own strained attempt to identify him with the mechanist school. And she makes no attempt to understand Trotsky’s theory of the Thermidorean counter-revolution in Soviet politics, which is vital to understanding the social basis of the counter-revolution in Soviet science.

Unlike Trotsky, Sheehan rejects the notion of a “river of blood” separating Stalinism from genuine Bolshevism. This means that Sheehan is at times both overcritical of Lenin and undercritical of Stalin. At one point she blames “aspects of Bolshevik revolutionary traditions” such as “an insurrectionist mentality, an intolerance towards those who opposed them in good faith, a tendency to subordinate means to ends.” And she sometimes implies that the harsh tone Lenin used in some of his polemics facilitated Stalinism. But at other times, she seems to be making excuses for Stalinism, with comments like “To a degree, perhaps, it was the enormity of their efforts that dictated the enormity of their mistakes. Those who dare little make fewer mistakes and those who dare much make many.”

The Russian Revolution had overthrown capitalism and landlordism, establishing a planned economy and workers’ democracy. The Stalinist bureaucracy was able to develop because of the isolation of the Revolution, but soon crystalized into a social force in its own right. The planned economy remained, and many of the problems with science under capitalism were overcome. But science under Stalinism was shaped in the interests of the Stalinist bureaucracy just as science under capitalism is shaped by the interests of the capitalist class. The bureaucracy relied on scientific development when it was directly necessary to developing the productive forces. This resulted in a massive expansion of scientific education in the Soviet Union rivalling the United States. But the numerous bureaucratic zigzags and accompanying purges saw some of the worst pseudo-scientific excesses being peddled in the name of Marxism.
International Debates

The positive impact of the Russian Revolution and the negative impact of the Stalinist counter-revolution weren’t confined to the Soviet Union itself. The Russian Revolution spurred the formation of the Communist International in 1919, bringing revolutionary Marxism to a wider international audience. Under Stalinism, however, this institution was converted into an arm of Soviet foreign policy. Outside the Soviet Union, however, it was still possible for independent Marxist forces to challenge the Stalinist line. But not all of these forces were equal.

Academic trends in Marxism developed that rejected the Stalinist caricatures of science. But these trends tended to throw the baby out with the bathwater, dismissing any role for Marxism in scientific understanding. In Europe, trends associated with Karl Korsch, György Lukács, and the “left communists” – who Lenin polemicized against – launched a neo-Hegelian revival, championing dialectics, but rejecting the more materialist aspects of Marxist thought. In America, a group of academics independent of the Communist International formed around Max Eastman and Sidney Hook, which sought to meld Marxist politics with the pragmatist philosophy of John Dewey. These philosophers were very much in favor of science, but saw dialectics as a mystical hangover from Hegel that had to be discarded for Marxism to be truly scientific.

From opposite directions, these two academic trends converged on a hostility to Friedrich Engels, especially his Dialectics of Nature. Hook argued that Marx was abandoning the dialectics of his youth and moving towards pragmatism, but that Engels insisted on smuggling it back in. Lukács, on the other hand, argued that Engels failed to truly grasp Marx’s dialectics by trying to smuggle in natural science, which Lukács identified with positivism. These diametrically opposed critiques of Engels had an unfortunate impact on later generations of academic Marxism, where Marx was twisted into being an advocate of whatever philosophical fad was popular at the time, while Engels was charged with smuggling in whatever aspects of Marxism were at odds with that philosophical fad.

But there were others, like Trotsky, who challenged the Stalinist distortions of dialectical materialism, while defending genuine dialectical materialism from the attacks of the academics. By 1940 the conflict between the Trotskyists and the American pragmatist Marxists featured in an open conflict within the Trotskyist movement.

Sheehan mentions Trotsky’s defense of genuine dialectical materialism, and credits other Trotskyist philosophers like George Novack and Pierre Naville for their contributions. But her coverage of these debates is fairly skimpy. Her coverage of the debates in Europe is much more fruitful, and brings up an often-ignored flourishing of Marxism among scientists in 1930s Britain that made significant contributions to advancing a dialectical approach to science.

At the 1931 presentation of Soviet scientists at the Second International Congress of the History of Science and Technology in London, the most prominent figure to take inspiration from this was J.D. Bernal, a pioneer in X-ray crystallography and molecular biology. He became famous for his writings on the history of science. Bernal stressed the powerful boost given to science by the rise of capitalism. But the very scientific revolution unleashed by capitalism had begun to outgrow capitalism. In Bernal’s Britain, scientific research was being deprived of funding under the impact of the depression. In neighboring Germany, science had been converted into a tool of Nazi barbarism. And, in spite of the scientific progress of capitalism, pseudoscience and anti-science ideas continue to proliferate to this day. Only the overthrow of capitalism and the establishment of socialism would allow science to reach its full potential.

Sheehan also points to the figures of J.B.S. Haldane and Christopher Cauldwell. Haldane was a biologist who became acquainted with Marxist philosophy during a visit to the Soviet Union. Much of his work continued in the tradition of Engels’ Dialectics of Nature but from the perspective of a full-time scientist. Along with the Soviet scientist A.I. Oparin, he formulated the Oparin-Haldane thesis concerning the origin of life. This thesis held that the early earth developed a “prebiotic soup” of organic compounds that could allow life to come into being given an appropriate energy source. As this new life dominated the earth, they altered their environment, causing the prebiotic soup to give way to the environment we’re more familiar with. This is now a commonly accepted thesis that was one of the first contributions to science resulting from a conscious application of dialectical materialism, rather than “unconscious dialectics.”

Cauldwell, unlike Bernal and Haldane, wasn’t a research scientist, instead working as a technical editor for an aeronautics journal. But he took a wide interest all manner of science, art and Marxism. He put forward a unified critique of a wide range of seemingly contradictory bourgeois cultural and philosophical ideas. He described a growing separation of science and philosophy, with science devolving into a crude positivism, and philosophy being subsumed into anti-science mysticism. The controversies about the “crisis in physics” were a consequence of new scientific discoveries being filtered through these inadequate bourgeois ideas. And, in contrast to the Stalinists, he pointed out how embracing the new developments in physics was not only compatible with dialectical materialism, but easier to grasp from a dialectical perspective.

Unlike Trotsky, this school of British Marxist scientists never made a decisive break with Stalinism. Their philosophical views were at odds with official Stalinist principles and more in touch with genuine Marxism. But organizationally, they remained affiliated to the Communist Party. This caused some mental gymnastics when confronted with the reality of Stalinism. When engaging in the scientific debates in British society, they were all willing to staunchly defend the legitimacy of genetics against the Lysenkoist distortions. But when confronted with the Soviet suppression of critics of Lysenkoism, they tended to make awkward excuses to avoid taking a stand. And, like Sheehan herself, they lacked Trotsky’s clear understanding of what was actually going on in the Soviet Union. Nonetheless they represented some of the first instances of scientists actively fusing their knowledge in both science and Marxism.
Relevance Today

Sheehan’s History ends in 1948. This date was picked because it served as a hundredth anniversary of the publishing of the Communist Manifesto, making it a centenary of Marxism in a sense. It also marked the consolidation of the Cold War and the entrenchment of the Stalinist distortions of science. In the west, academic Marxism also saw its own entrenchment, with the Lukács-inspired hostility to science burying the legacy of figures like Bernal, Haldane, and Cauldwell. And establishment academia in the west was able to consolidate a full-scale rejection of Marxism in science.

Even without the benefit of Marxist philosophy, science has continued to make breakthrough after breakthrough under capitalism. But while most scientists don’t consciously adopt a dialectical philosophy, modern science can’t function without dialectics. As such the achievements of science under capitalism remain a product of unconscious dialectics. The resolution of the “crisis of physics” could only be accomplished through a dialectical interpenetration of opposites. Highly successful scientific theories like quantum physics, plate tectonics, and the concept of an ecosystem are a confirmation of the Marxist approach.

But capitalism has still proved unable to resolve its contradictions, including in the field of science. In 1969, a new wave of radical scientists was born under the name Science for the People. Science for the People revived interest in Bernal, Haldane, and Cauldwell, while updating their views for the political and scientific problems of a new period of struggle. This produced a revival of Marxism in science, around figures such as Stephen Jay Gould, Richard Levins, Richard Lewontin, and Stephen Rose. Scientific developments such as Gould’s theory of punctuated equilibrium show what can be achieved through conscious dialectics in science.

The collapse of Stalinism and the neo-liberal counter-revolution set Marxism back once again. But people are once more taking to struggle. And science has become much more intertwined with these struggles. Capitalism’s role in the global climate crisis reveals more sharply the need for a socialist approach to science. Donald Trump’s attacks on science forced scientists to take to the streets in record numbers. Previously accepted undialectical caricatures of science, like biological determinism, have increasingly been wielded as weapons of the far-right. And the adjunctification of academia has seen scientists increasingly entering the ranks of the proletariat and engaging in labor struggles more traditionally associated with the Marxist movement.

For scientists moving into struggle, or for any activists looking into the political and philosophical implications of their struggles in the field of science, Helena Sheehan’s history provides a useful guide.

 

Bogdanov, Technocracy and Socialism (2007)



From the April 2007 issue of the Socialist Standard

The terms “Bolshevism” and “Leninism” are usually treated as synonyms. In view of Lenin’s enormous influence over the Bolshevik party, that might seem fair enough. But in fact Lenin did have political and intellectual rivals inside his own party. The most important of these non-Leninist Bolsheviks was Alexander Bogdanov (1873—1928).

Bogdanov was a man of many talents and interests. His formal training was in medicine and psychiatry. He invented an original philosophy that he called “tectology” and is now regarded as a precursor of systems theory (synergetics). He was also a Marxian economist, a theorist of culture, a popular science fiction writer, and of course a political activist. Even today most of his work is not available in English. The only book devoted to him is Zenovia Sochor’s study of his ideas about culture (Revolution and Culture: The Bogdanov-Lenin Controversy, Cornell University Press 1988).

A volume of Bogdanov’s science fiction has, however, appeared in English (Red Star: The First Bolshevik Utopia, translated by Charles Rougle and edited by Loren R. Graham and Richard Stites, Indiana University Press 1984). Here we have two novels set on Mars (Red Star and Engineer Menni), a poem “A Martian Stranded on Earth,” and interpretative essays by each of the editors. Red Star recounts how Martians take the Russian Bolshevik Leonid to their home planet to learn about the communist society there and act as a link between earth and Mars.

Engineer Menni is also set on Mars, but at an earlier stage, shortly before the transition from capitalism to communism. Menni’s mission in life is to design Mars’ great canals – it was widely believed at the time that there are canals on Mars – and organize and manage their construction.

Cult of the engineer?

Both Russian and Western commentators have called Bogdanov an advocate of “technocracy” and the promoter of a “cult of the engineer.”

Thus Richard Stites speaks of his “celebration of technocratic power [and] the technical intelligentsia.” On the surface this assessment seems justified. Engineer Menni was popular among Soviet planners at the time of the first Five Year Plan, and Menni is certainly a heroic figure with whom any aspiring technocrat might readily identify.

But you do not have to search very hard to find evidence that suggests a different assessment. In Red Star Bogdanov presents communist Mars as a society beset by serious problems – by no means a utopia. Technology is a major source of these problems. Leonid discovers, for instance, that some workers are so mesmerized by the machinery they operate that they refuse to stop working and have to be forced to rest. And Nella, Menni’s abandoned lover, sings a song in which she complains that for all his virtues Menni is lacking in compassion:

“His heart is of ice, no pain does it feel

For the creatures brought low by Fate . . .

The tears of the wretches cast into the fray

Warm not his heart of stone.”

The Martian political system portrayed in Red Star – little explicit detail is provided – does indeed seem to be technocratic rather than democratic. Thus, the speakers at a conference convened to consider Martian colonization of earth are an astronautical engineer, a physician, and a mathematician (who argues in favour of annihilating all earthlings and is later killed by a distraught Leonid). Martians in managerial positions move around in flying “gondolas” that do not seem to be available to ordinary Martians. (If they were, air traffic control would be a nightmare.) This is not a society that I would wish to call socialist or communist even though the exchange of commodities has been abolished and production is for use.

In Engineer Menni we find a clue as to why the revolution has given birth to a technocratic society. A workers’ delegate at a trade union congress bemoans the fact that the workers’ ignorance prevents them from judging matters for themselves and puts them at the mercy of experts, whom they have no choice but to believe.

Technocracy or socialism?

Both Bogdanov’s fiction and his political writings as presented by Sochor suggest that he expected the coming revolution against capitalism to lead to a technocratic society. This was because the workers lacked the knowledge and initiative to seize control of social affairs for themselves. One reason fort his situation was the hierarchical and authoritarian nature of the capitalist production process. Another was the hierarchical and authoritarian mode of organization of the Bolshevik party, although Bogdanov considered such organization necessary and inevitable – he was a Bolshevik, after all.

This, however, was not a prospect that Bogdanov welcomed or idealized. He knew that real socialism (or communism) could only be a fully democratic society. And he knew that only a highly cultured and knowledgeable working class could achieve real socialism. That is why questions of culture and education were so central to his thought and work. The emphasis on knowledge and understanding as prerequisites for real socialism (as opposed to technocratic pseudo-socialism) is common ground that he shares with us in the world socialist movement.

While Bogdanov remained loyal to the Bolshevik regime in Russia until the end of his life, his ideas were deeply subversive of the society over which that regime presided. Bogdanov’s ideas were the inspiration for a dissident group called “Workers’ Truth” that was active for a time in the early 1920s (although it appears that Bogdanov did not have personal ties with them). In their manifesto, “Workers’ Truth” declared that the old bourgeoisie had been replaced as masters of production by “the technical intelligentsia under state capitalism”; the Communist Party had become the party of this intelligentsia, which was the nucleus of a rising new bourgeoisie.

Stefan (WSPUS)

 

Bloodwork: Alexander Bogdanov (1873–1928)

Chloe Wilson

Joint first prize ($7,500), 2016 Griffith University Josephine Ulrick Poetry Prize

  1. Rituals

We discussed the possibilities
while brooding over strategy – the chairman took
my rook and asked – but
                       how alike are we to calves?

I said, do you mean before or after
slaughter? The fish-gasp of his laughter.
            My queen and king

were done for.            We started over.
            He said – how about
                                  in the moment

                                  we move from one state
            to the other? I lacked a satisfactory

            answer, said that dog to dog
            is always preferable,

                                  but it seemed harmless

to remember Denys, who parted
                       the carotid arteries of several
            farmyard residents,
                                  and transferred their blood to men
            with great success; there was, for instance

that boy, dumb in body, who took a lamb’s blood
and revived, pissing out
                       a choler, black and shining
                       like his hair.

Years later, they handed me
            the chairman’s exsanguinated head, said –
            do what you might to revive him.

 

  1. Spirits

They say: grind up tiger teeth,
                                  and stir them into tea,
                       for courage.

Or: owl eyes, swallowed entire,
                       will bring vision
            to the hunstman
who wishes to see in the dark.

One thinks
            of the Iroquois chief
                       who, impressed by Brébeuf’s tenacity
                                  under red-hot hatchets,
            saw fit to eat his heart.

                       It is the same, old knowledge –
whichever spirit
            slips into the circulation
                       will exert its influence.

 

  1. Red Star

We have been undertaking the exchanges.

My wife’s face expands, a rehydrated
                                             apricot. My hairline
                       retakes territories it had conceded.
            We reach for one another
                                             in wonder.

Blood. One more type
            of private property
                                  to be abolished. In the paradise
I’ve designed, it circulates
            like money. All the young

are rich as sultans. I imagine
            their skins
                       taut as fresh-picked grapes.

I imagine setting them out
            in the sun,
            the concentrated sweetness
as they wrinkle; I think
                       of spitting out the pips.

 

  1. Invaders

Blood is a jungle. In a single slide, observe
            the tangle of thugs and roughnecks,

            their nightly riots. Foreigners
may be swept along
            with the pressure-current.

My volunteer had a wheal I did not see.
            A proboscis had gone searching
            through his person, left him teeming

                       with looters
                                  who think nothing
                       of the edifice which they deface.

            A shame. Days later, I am slick and glistening
            with fever. It is a comfort, however,

to think of how I flourish
            throughout another’s vascular forest. He will
                       wake, convalesce, recover,

            not thinking to ask what or whom
might be zooming through the florets
            of his brain matter –

                       accepting the arrival

of a desire to amass flammables,
            or pen the seditious letter – that needling
insistence; that new,
                       communicable itch.