Wednesday, December 29, 2021

Capitalists are Dispensable, Laborers Are Not


 
 DECEMBER 28, 2021Facebook

Photograph Source: Mark Dixon – CC BY 2.0

“If you set to work to believe everything,
you will tire out the believing-muscles of your mind,
and then you’ll be so weak you won’t be able
to believe the simplest true things.”

– Lewis Carroll

Capitalists—qua owners of capital—are dispensable, but laborers are not.

This thesis flows from a neglected asymmetry between capitalists and laborers. The capitalist does not stand in the same relation to capital and the services of capital as a laborer does with respect to his laboring capacities and the services of these capacities. This distinction goes unacknowledged by neoclassical economists as well as economists of other persuasions. If this is because they have concluded that this is of no consequence, we offer some arguments to the contrary.

There is irony in this thesis even as capitalism threatens to render laborers ‘useless,’ that is, replace them with intelligent machines faster than it creates new jobs. But this is not the place to address this irony.

Why are capitalists dispensable?

Consider a series of relations moving from a capitalist to his capital, and from capital to the services of capital. Next examine another series moving from a laborer to his laboring capacities, and from these capacities to the diverse services of these capacities, also known as the services of labor. There exist important differences between the two series.

There exists no integral—or, if you prefer, visceral—connection between the capitalist and his capital or between the capitalist and the services of capital. Capital and the services of capital are wholly external to the capitalist qua owner of capital; their relationship to the capitalist is merely legal so that a capitalist can be physically separated from his capital and the services of his capital. If the capitalist prefers leisure to work or lacks the requisite managerial skills, he can delegate the task of running his enterprise to hired managers. Once the capitalist appoints a manager to run his enterprise, he could be soaking the sun inside one of the many craters on the moon while his enterprise continues to produce goods or services somewhere in Agawam, Massachusetts. All this notwithstanding, at the end of every year or every quarter, this capitalist will receive the profits or carry the losses of his enterprise. This is his return for risking his funds to organize production.

Now consider an economy whose capital has been transferred to the workers in each enterprise. The workers in each enterprise form a worker-cooperative; they collectively own its capital, vote to elect a workers’ council who then appoint managers, or elect the managers directly. In addition, each WC is free to borrow funds from deposit banks or tax-funded investment banks. Each WC is also free to sell some fraction of its fixed capital should this not be needed; the proceeds from this sale may be used to pay off loans, deposited in a bank as a reserve fund against rainy days, or allocated to research and development.

Each worker cooperative may choose its modus vivendi and its goals. At first, therefore, a variety of worker cooperatives may emerge, with different goals and structures; they may be more or less egalitarian; some may work primarily with fixed wages, others with a combination of fixed wages and shares in the coop’s residual. Some may give greater weight to steady employment, others to higher wages. It is difficult to say, which types of cooperatives may emerge as winners. Collectively, the cooperatives may set some limits to the goals, and the governance and the reward structures of the coops to ensure the viability of the system as a whole.

In one stroke then, we have created a market economy without any capitalists as the term is understood in a capitalist economy. Production in this economy is organized by worker cooperatives, whose policies are formulated by a management periodically elected by workers. The workers in each enterprise are free to set the rules under which they work; they are also free to leave one WC and join another. However, the capital of any enterprise is not traded, nor does it move when any worker leaves the enterprise.

In a splendid piece of circular reasoning, neoclassical economists justify private ownership of capital on the ground that it is the capitalist who organizes production. This is a non sequitur. The capitalist organizes production precisely because he is a capitalist: he commands his own or borrowed funds that allow him to do so. In an economy consisting of worker cooperatives, teams of workers could organize production with funds borrowed from deposit banks or tax-funded investment banks.

It may be argued that the co-ops cannot match the performance of corporations because they have no skin in the game. This is not true. Unlike workers who receive fixed wages, the members of WCs may receive all or some fraction of their income that is tied to their co-op’s residual. Since they share in the coop’s decision-making, co-op members are more likely than wage-workers to identify with their enterprise. In themselves, these factors may help to reduce shirking. In addition, shirkers in co-ops are likely to come under moral censure from non-shirkers. If free-riding is seen as a problem, the WCs can empower the management to monitor the performance of members and work out rules for dismissing habitual shirkers. Collectively, co-ops may discourage shirking by discounting the earnings of new members who have a record of shirking. Shirkers may also be given the chance to expunge their record by improving their performance.

Since the capitalist is physically separable from his capital, this creates the possibility of separating ownership of capital in an enterprise from control over it. In medieval times, we observe trade partnerships in the Middle East—known as qirad in Arabic—where some partners advanced capital to traders who managed the task of conducting the trade. In 1932, Adolph Berle and Gardiner Means showed that ownership and control of most large-scale enterprises in the United States had ceased to reside in the same hands.

In activities without significant economies of scale and high costs of supervision, the capitalist may lend and/or rent his capital to workers and let them organize production. In agriculture, we find landlords who rent their lands to peasants instead of hiring wage-workers to organize production. During the late eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, capitalists in Britain set up textile factories with work benches that workers could rent to produce yarn and cloth on their own account. It is also common for laborers lacking capital to rent cars, trucks and rickshaws to produce transport services. Others rent space in commercial buildings to organize retail businesses.

A laborer cannot be physically separated from his working capacities or the services of his working capacities.

A laborer’s working capacities include his body, the metabolism that converts food into energy, his cognitive powers, memory, will, emotions, skills, intuition, and his powers of reasoning, sight, speech, hearing, taste and touch. The execution of any task by a worker in real time—whether this entails digging a trench, a sitar recital, performing surgery, crafting a violin, or time spent solving a yet unsolved mathematical conundrum—is the joint product of various manifestations or services of his working capacities.

Under a wage-contract, however, a laborer may sell the services of his working capacities to an employer. In addition, a self-employed person with access to some capital may employ his working capacities to produce services (such as haircuts) that he sells directly to buyers. Alternatively, as a carpenter, he may employ his working capacities to saw, bend, carve, plane, sand, screw together, and polish timber into chairs, and then sell the chairs for a profit. In both cases, the laborer, will likely receive the market wage for his labor and a similar return on the capital he employs in his enterprise.

Some exceptions to the inseparability of a laborer from his laboring capacities may also be noted. If medical technology permits, he may sell or donate his organs or tissues for transplantation to another person. However, a person is unlikely to consent to such transplantations, except when this promises to save the life of a loved one. Of course, without the living person’s consent, or after he dies or is killed, the possibilities become endless.

The first asymmetry we have just described leads to another. 

The separability of the capitalist from his capital nudges us to explore egalitarian re-arrangements of the ownership of capital. Should such rearrangements occur, the capitalists will only lose their claim to the surplus of capitalist enterprises, but they will retain all their rights as citizens and as members of WCs in the new economy. Should they also possess some valuable skills, the WCs will recognize and reward these skills without any prejudice arising from their past history as capitalists.

On the other hand, a laborer cannot be separated from his laboring capacities without also losing his freedom. The capitalist can take ownership of the laboring capacities of legally free laborers only after he takes ownership of their persons for some part of a day, that is, by turning them into wage-slaves.

Importantly, the absence of any integral or visceral connection between the capitalist and his capital points to the potential for reorganizing the ownership of capital on an egalitarian basis. It would be disingenuous to think that the capitalists themselves are not aware of this potential for egalitarian rearrangements of the ownership of capital. In addition, we may surmise that the capitalists know that the workers too—perhaps, with help from their protagonists in the intellectual classes—are aware of this vulnerability.

Given all of the above, we may surmise that capitalists have always been at work—no doubt with help from self-serving economists—to obfuscate this vulnerability and, simultaneously, to harness the coercive powers of the state to protect their pivotal position in the capitalist system. Since the actual use of coercion is costly, the capitalists employ all the forces at their command to convince the workers of the superiority of an economic system based on the private ownership of the means of production. However, should the workers start questioning this ‘natural order,’ the capitalists are prepared to call on the machinery of the state—especially the courts, police and prisons—to knock the workers until they back the capitalist narrative.

Which of the two classes—capitalists or workers—is likely to organize production in a capitalist economy? 

In the 1950s, after nearly a century of mathematical ‘modling,’ neoclassical economists concluded that they had worked out the contours of an imaginary economy that would serve as the ideological fortress of capitalism. Markets in this economy instantaneously reach an equilibrium that is unique, stable and efficient in the sense that no person can be made better off without making at least one person worse off. Capital and labor in this economy receive their just deserts: that is to say, there is no exploitation of labor. In the words of Paul Samuelson, in this economy “it really did not matter who hires whom; so have labor hire ‘capital.’”

The message of the neoclassicals to the capitalists is: Don’t let your hard work as bosses give you a bad conscience. It gives you no advantage. The message to the workers is: Why bother with organizing production; let the capitalists worry about this. Enjoy your hassle-free life as workers; you have nothing to gain from losing your chains. These charming results hold only in perfectly competitive markets in which capitalists can costlessly write and enforce complete employment contracts.

In the real world, however, production is nearly always organized by capitalist bosses. Hurling what he thinks is a challenge to Karl Marx,  David Landes asks “if [capitalist] bosses make (cream off) so much money, why shouldn’t boss-free enterprises (cooperatives, collectives, small self-employed workers, and the like) be able to outdo those capitalistic units that pay so heavy a toll to owners and managers?” Landes imagines that he is setting up a test of the feasibility of workers organizing production. He is challenging boss-free enterprises to organize production in capitalist economies under property rights, institutions and rules established by capitalists. Now, since worker co-ops do not—with rare exceptions—organize production in capitalist economies, this supposedly ‘proves’ that they cannot compete with capitalists in organizing production.

Landes forgets that workers cannot organize production because they have been stripped of the means of production. Since they cannot offer any collateral, they also cannot borrow money or rent capital. Moreover, financing the establishment of WCs is not only a financial issue. The economic and political power of capitalists is built around their class monopoly over production. Why would they dilute this class monopoly by lending capital to workers? It is unlikely that capitalist guilt over exploitation of workers ever reaches the point at which they become willing to commit hara-kiri.

Is the separation of capitalists from capital unjust?

Can any economic system be considered just that has a tendency to place—and often ends up placing—the means of production in the hands of a tiny minority of capitalists, thereby endowing them with the power to organize production not in the interests of the workers or society but exclusively in the interests of the capitalists. Depending on conditions in the labor market, and driven by the profit imperative, the capitalist may hire and fire workers at will. In addition, he may demand that his hired hands put in long hours of work, six days a week, quicken their pace of work to keep up with the machines, and take no breaks in the workplace, even if they have to piss in a bottle or wear diapers.

In a capitalist economy, moreover, workers are disposable, unless they have acquired skills specific to the enterprise in which they work; they may be laid off or fired whenever they are not needed. Can an economic system be just that nearly always fails to provide some workers with employment, and during a depression may fail to provide employment to as much as a third of the workers; when it does provide employment, many of these jobs may not offer the workers a living wage. Can an economic system be humane whose commitment to profit-making demands that workers be fired when they fall sick or are injured even when the sickness and injury are caused by hazards of the work and the workplace? It is ironic that while wage-workers in capitalist economies are legally free and wage-work is considered to be superior to slavery, the capitalists do not have any intrinsic interest in the livelihood and health of their workers that slave-owners have in their slaves and their families.

Similarly, while wage-workers are legally free, they lose their freedom the moment they enter the workplace. The neoclassical economist will predictably protest that a wage-worker remains free even at work since he is free to leave his present job whenever he wishes; if he does not quit that is because he chooses to stay. Sorry: this is a flawed inference. The neoclassical economist is always liberal in making assumptions; when he needs a can opener he just assumes that he has one. Hence, neoclassical economics assumes that workers face no costs in moving to another job that he prefers over his current job.

However, the ability to switch jobs at will does not overcome the lack of freedom at the workplace. A worker cannot escape the lack of freedom at the workplace because this is an unavoidable condition of capitalist employment, unless the nature of a job makes monitoring of work very costly. The lack of freedom at work cannot be blamed on technology; the capitalists have been choosing technology, layout of factories and offices, and work organization that truncate worker autonomy. Bosses can monitor their employees’ pace of work, even when they work remotely.

Conservatives and liberals are likely to view with alarm any talk about the rearrangement of capitalist property rights in the means of production.

Although such alarm is to be expected from the historical beneficiaries of capital accumulation over the last half a millennium, this shows societal amnesia about the horrendous crimes against humanity that attended, and still attend, the expropriation of great masses of humans—men, women, children and the unborn—to finance and support the creation of capitalists and capitalist power in Western Europe and North America. Karl Marx applied the moniker of ‘primitive accumulation’ to the “historical process of divorcing the producer from the means of production.”

The capitalist organization of British agriculture, which began in the late fifteenth century, was accomplished over the next three centuries through successive expropriations of the peasantry either by force or through laws passed by the largest landowners—formerly feudal lords—in the British parliament. The free peasantry that had emerged in England by the late fourteenth century earned a living from cultivating strips of arable land, but they also depended crucially on access to commons for firewood, pasturing their cattle, gathering berries and mushrooms, and catching game and fish. Once the growth of woolen manufactures in Flanders raised the price of wool, English landowners began to privatize the commons, either by force or passing enclosure acts that denied peasants access to the commons, and converted them into sheep pastures; this forced some peasants to seek wage-work in agriculture, while others abandoned their lands to seek wage-work in the towns. In addition, the large landowners also began to enforce gaming laws to ride roughshod over the farms of peasants resulting in losses to their crops.

Next consider a historical rearrangement of property rights during the nineteenth century that is more germane to the subject of this essay. I am referring to the large-scale separation—in the Americas during the nineteenth century—of a very important class of capitalists from their capital invested in slaves. In August 1791, the black slaves in Saint-Domingue—a French colony that was a source of immense profits to France—began a successful rebellion against slave-owning capitalists—who after defeating two massive invasions ordered by Napoleon Bonaparte in 1801 and 1802, declared the establishment in 1804 of the Republic of Haiti ruled by former black slaves. Do we object to this transfer of property rights in slaves from plantations owners to the slaves themselves?

In the nineteenth century, we encounter several more examples of the separation of capitalists from their capital invested in slaves. In 1833, Britain transferred the ownership rights of capitalists in humans to the humans themselves in nearly all its colonial possessions. Some of the northern states in the USA, following the War of Independence in 1776, began passing laws that effected similar transfers of ownership rights in slaves. In 1861, in the midst of the American Civil War, slavery was also abolished in the Southern States. Brazil, perhaps the largest slave-based economy in history, abolished slavery in 1888. In general, where slavery was abolished under law, the cash compensation was less than the market value of the slaves.

The principal results of this essay are easily summarized.

The capitalist is physically separable from the capital that he owns, but the laborer cannot be parted from his laboring capacities.

The first part of the previous statement establishes the feasibility of separating the capitalist from his capital. Indeed, the capitalist (qua capitalist) is a rentier since he does not contribute the services of any of his present working capacities to the enterprise in which he owns capital. The capitalist’s claim to profits is rooted in a legal relationship, not an economic relationship.

Au contraire, the services of a laborer are inseparable from his person. This means that in order to maximize his profits, the capitalist who hires labor must gain control over the laborer’s person and his working capacities in the workplace and—if necessary and feasible—off the workplace. In other words, the capitalist logic demands that the laborer be stripped of his autonomy once he enters the workplace. Although the worker is free in theory to choose his employer, this freedom does not restore the autonomy that he enjoyed in his work and workplace as a self-employed peasant, artisan, peddler or shopkeeper.

A clear-eyed focus on the asymmetry in the two binaries—the separability of the capitalist from capital and inseparability of the laborer from his working capacities—suggests significant gains that are likely to flow from an alternative organization of production that transfers ownership and control over capital from capitalist enterprises to worker cooperatives.

A detailed discussion of these gains is a subject for another essay. However, broadly speaking, these gains are likely to flow from two forms of democratization that will attend the transfer of capital from the capitalists to the workers. First, there is the political democratization that will flow from the transformation of the capitalist enterprises to worker cooperatives. A political system that grows out of the interests and actions of workers and worker co-ops is unlikely to be hijacked by sectional interests.

Secondly, there is the democratization in the workplace. A variety of benefits are likely to flow to workers from the establishment of co-ops. These may include sharing by members in policy-making, creation of a culture of egalitarianism, improvements in working conditions, equal access of all members and their families to education, health and social services, less hierarchy in the organization of work, sharing and phasing out of tedious work, and greater income inequality. An economy consisting of worker co-ops will nurture cooperation, in the workplace and outside it. Once profits are dethroned as the only or chief objective driving production and technological change, the economy will have a chance to redirect its focus from endless capital accumulation towards a thousand improvements in the quality of life for everyone.

M. SHAHID ALAM is professor of economics at Northeastern University. This is an excerpt from his forthcoming book, Israeli Exceptionalism: The Destabilizing Logic of Zionism (Macmillan, November 2009). Contact me at alqalam02760@yahoo.com.

A Socialist Defense of Vaccine Mandates


 
 DECEMBER 28, 2021

Facebook

I was slightly surprised to see that Richard Wolff opposed vaccine mandates. C. Derick Varn thought Wolff wanted to support the position of the working class and this was why he opposes the mandates. I don’t agree with Wolff but it got me thinking about the assumptions around the persistence of the pandemic. Wolff is right to question the common assumptions but he comes up with the wrong solution.

The reason I support vaccine mandates is that all policies are in a vacuum. It may very well be a violation of certain freedom to mandate vaccines and in a socialist utopia on our horizon we would not have a profit making machine that creates pandemics nor would we have an authoritarian state to mandate treatment for them by profit-making companies. But in our world, where our immediate choices are capitalism with vaccines and capitalism without vaccines I’ll take the former.

Our lives aren’t free under the current tyranny of the employer-employee relationship, according to Mr. Wolff. He’s correct. What’s one more unfreedom to add to the list when it saves the lives of the working class?

Noam Chomsky has a better argument in favor of vaccine mandates. Professor Chomsky compares vaccine mandates to traffic lights. Sure, in a vacuum traffic lights restrict freedom. But they also make us safer.

To counter Wolff let’s be more specific with this analogy. If the assumption of the opposition to the vaccine mandate is that it oppresses the working class more than the ruling class then let’s say the same dynamic holds for traffic lights. In fact the same dynamic holds for everything, including both sides of this debate. If someone runs a traffic light they get a ticket. Billionaires wouldn’t be punished by a small fine. A poor person could not be able to pay the fine, or they could miss a bill or go into debt or jail.

However, if we simply gave freedom without considering class the same thing happens. Poor people don’t have affordable health insurance in case of a car accident without lights. They’re more likely to be on the road working and more likely to be charged with a crime for running someone over, assuming we still had laws about that in this hypothetical.

The question Chomsky poses for us is not who is worse off from a policy, the working class or the ruling class. Because the answer for every policy is that the working class will be treated worse. The question is which is better for the working class, a world with traffic lights or a world without? Assuming of course that abolishing traffic lights wouldn’t lead to a socialist revolution. If that policy could lead us to such grand heights then we could have an argument about it.

I’ll apply the same logic to the vaccine mandates. Yes the rich can more easily cheat their way out of the mandates and they are more likely to have money independent of a job requirement. On the other hand it’s irrefutable that poor people are far more likely to die of coronavirus than rich people are. So the question is the same. Which is better for the working class; a world with people vaccinated or a world where people can choose not to be?

If we assume Richard Wolff is right, and that today is not a time of freedom for most people because of their relationship to the capitalist class, then it seems to me that freedom to choose to get a vaccine is a small liberty in a world where you can’t choose whether or not you have protection from the virus. Either way freedom is violated. The question is which is worse for freedom?

If Wolff is saying we spend too much energy trying to get fascists vaccinated and not enough energy to provide access of the vaccine to the working class then I would agree with most of his framing. It seems to me that the obsession over getting American fascists vaccinated while completely letting the entire rest of the world get infected reflects the ruling class’s attitude in general about the Republican’s small and bourgeois base.

Remember how much effort was wasted spewing nonsense about how Democrats just needed to cater a little more to the fascists and they would win? All of this while the working class, who don’t or can’t vote at least half the time, is completely ignored. The same can be said for the vaccination question. There is no effort by governments or corporations to vaccinate the vast majority of the global working class and the entire effort is spent convincing American fascists that they should listen to liberals.

There is so much cynicism around vaccinating the working class that left liberals are proclaiming Omicron, by all accounts a far more contagious version of the virus, some sort of victory. This position bothers me for a couple reasons. The assumption is that this variant is more contagious but is not as bad for your health. Perhaps. But this second part is less certain. What happens for the following variant? If the virus continues to get more contagious won’t we all be infected? Isn’t this the exact same position as the conservative herd immunity proposition that renders people disposable rather than address the pandemic through policy?

What does this supposed new reality of extremely contagious virus mean for the unvaccinated?

In a similar vein while the virus itself might be the most damaging part of the pandemic for the rich, the poor face an even greater economic threat if the pandemic continues. I’ll explain why this makes opposing vaccine mandates a reactionary position in a minute. My first point on this front is that the implication of a more contagious disease even if it is less deadly means more economic shutdowns and thus more money being funneled upwards to the rich.

The reactionary position is that opening up the economy saves the working class. This isn’t true. That’s because ultimately the economies running in a way that allows people to continue to work regular hours relies on people voluntarily spending. If the pandemic persists then the economy won’t open up because people will choose not to buy things for their own protection, not because the government prohibits them from doing so. Therefore opposing vaccine mandates on the basis that it helps the working class makes no sense because a prolonged pandemic just squeezes the working class more.

Now someone may respond that freedom to not take the vaccine is freedom for the working class. Even if that is their position then I have to ask why not advocate for the majority of the world to get that same choice of whether or not to take the vaccine. The reality is that most people are forced not to get the vaccine while very few people are forced to get it.

Now comes the rebuttal. These drug companies are all about making money! Yeah, duh. That’s why they don’t distribute the vaccines to most of the world where they can’t make a profit. The problem with capitalism isn’t necessarily that it makes faulty products.

Capitalism creates technological advances, including the vaccine. The issue is more that the technology can’t be distributed unless it’s done in a profitable way. Solar power is way cheaper than fossil fuels but it’s too cheap to make a profit off of. That’s why capitalism is stupid and the economy should be organized around human needs not profit. That’s the argument for socialism and on that logic alone I don’t know why one would be against vaccines.

Still let’s continue in good faith. The vaccines clearly aren’t keeping up with the virus in the way we would want. So new vaccines keep needing to be made and new profit is being made. These vaccine companies don’t want the pandemic to end because they make money from it continuing. So as all of this goes on not only do they lack the original incentive to vaccinate poor countries because that on its own this is not profitable but they also have a broader incentive not to vaccinate poorer countries because that keeps the pandemic going.

And yes I’m sure there are some medicinal methods that help combat the virus that isn’t profitable and therefore aren’t being distributed either under the logic of capitalism. I really doubt that any of them are nearly as effective as the vaccine but in the face of no distribution of the vaccine, we should not be opposed to looking at these alternative methods as supplements to our larger goal of universal vaccination.

Would a better goal be universal freedom of choice to vaccinate? I don’t know. It sounds so bourgeois to me. In the fascist USA we tend to define our ideal of liberal democracy not by the universalism of liberal democracy. Instead, liberal democracy is seen to be liberal democracy only when it bends backward to accommodate fascists who aren’t interested in liberal democracy. Giving those interested in abolishing liberal democracy an equal say to those who want it seems to be the way liberal democracy cannot sustain itself.

Likewise, I question if obscuring the main problem of vaccine distribution with a question of vaccine choice is really helping anyone. The pandemic continuing will have awful health and economic implications for the global working class. I think opposing vaccine mandates is the wrong answer but even worse, it’s the wrong question.

The term “working class” in the US is generally code for white male middle-class Americans, likely even small business owners. But I will use the word below without those assumptions.

The left should be for the working class, rather than frame itself as of the working class. Proclaiming that the left is of the working class denies people agency to make their own decisions. The working class relates to economic production and should be able to choose for itself, as a whole, what it wants. The task of the left is not to tail this position and decide for the working class what it wants.

The task of the left rather is to empower and support the working class, regardless of their political positions, real or imagined. In a democratic society the working class will dictate political economy, but in reality this seldom happens. However, no matter what else is going on the left should be for the working class rather than try to be of the working class as a form of postured authenticity.

I understand the left and working-class almost entirely overlap. My point is that the left is a political position while the working class is a class position. One can be both but they aren’t the same. Trying to have the left simply follow around an imaginary working class consensus not only most often misreads the working class but it also is by definition an apolitical position.

What the left should be doing is politics, for that is what the left is. The politics of the left should be to support the working class no matter who they are or what we think of them.

In this case, supporting the working class does not mean fulfilling bourgeois ideals of free choice but rather it means providing full access to vaccination in order to get people safe and healthy enough to confidently demand more from the capitalist class without fear of losing work, which is the leverage the working class has over the capitalists, who need to exploit the workers to compete with other capitalists.

A prolonged pandemic means that companies will continue to cut hours and wages sporadically, unions will run out of money, working people will organize less, travel to escape economic hardship will be restricted, violence against women will rise, and health care will be harder to access.

Opposing lockdowns, vaccine mandates and the like assumes that it is an authoritarian state that is pulling the strings behind these trends rather than people collectively taking less risks in order to protect their health. The overreach from the government comes from their handouts to corporations, including vaccine producers. Socialists generally oppose all authority, state included, upon the working class.

In that spirit, I oppose all authority of the left to represent the working class. Each person should have the right to represent themselves. Especially the working class. The left-wing position, in my opinion, is to get as many people protected from the virus as possible. Until I see material proof that vaccine mandates provide anywhere close to the same threat as the virus, I don’t see how there’s an argument.

Nick Pemberton writes and works from Saint Paul, Minnesota. He loves to receive feedback at pemberton.nick@gmail.com 

Russia plans cyberattacks on Ukraine's grid, banks and government - NYT


Source : 112 Ukraine

The United States and the United Kingdom sent cyberwar experts to Ukraine to better prepare it to deal with hacker attacks
21 December 2021


 AFP 

Russia is preparing a series of cyberattacks against the Ukrainian government, power grids, the banking system and other important sectors of the economy as The New York Times reported citing the American intelligence.

According to the US intelligence community, the goal of Russian President Vladimir Putin at the moment is not an invasion of Ukraine with 175,000 troops that he collects at the border, but cyberattacks aimed at damaging Ukrainian infrastructure. Such subversive actions against Ukraine will not require occupation of the country or physical attack and will avoid the sanctions that Western countries have promised to impose in the event of Russian aggression.

Moreover, hacker attacks on important areas of the Ukrainian economy and government agencies will certainly weaken President of Ukraine Volodymyr Zelensky and expose him to society as inept and defenseless. All this will create the basis either for the overthrow of the government and the establishment of a puppet power loyal to Russia, or it will prepare a pretext for a real attack on the country.

Related: Pegasus — the favorite cyber weapon of dictators

American officials cannot say with certainty that a military invasion will take place.

“The current assessment of the U.S. government is that he has not made a decision,” President Biden’s national security adviser Jake Sullivan said.

Russian cyber activity has been the focus of the White House, the CIA, the NSA, and the US Cyber Command, whose "cyber missions" are deployed to identify vulnerabilities around the world. The data was obtained from classified sources.

Therefore, the United States and the United Kingdom secretly dispatched cyber warfare experts to Ukraine to better prepare it to deal with hacker attacks.

Related: 1,7 mln cyberattacks carried out on Ukraine's state agencies during six months

While no government provided details, officials said the United States is considering a larger deployment, including US Cyber Command resources.

In a statement, the administration of US President Joe Biden said that the United States "has long supported Ukraine's efforts to strengthen cyber defense and increase its cyber resilience."

A British government spokesman said the assistance provided by Britain and its allies was defensive in nature.

American officials believe that the Russian cyber campaign against Ukraine has, in a sense, never stopped, although until recently it continued at a low level. However, American officials and experts note that over the past month, the number of malicious activities in the cyberspace of Ukraine has increased, even as public attention has been focused on the troop build-up.

“It’s a widespread campaign targeting numerous Ukrainian government agencies, including internal affairs — the national police — and their electric utilities,” leading investigator of Russian cyber activity and the chairman of Silverado Policy Accelerator Dmitri Alperovitch said.

Related: Ukraine's Security Service exposes $758,000 sceme of cyber protection funds embezzlement

According to him, the Russian leader views cyberattacks as "preparing the battlefield."

The Ukrainian power grid was created during the Soviet Union and is connected to Russia. It has been upgraded with Russian equipment. The program is as familiar to cybercriminals as to operators.

As we reported, a hacker who carried out DDoS (attacks on a computer system made with the intention of making computer resources inaccessible to the user) and spam attacks (mass mailing of commercials) and hacked websites was exposed.

 

The Future of Work Has Changed, and Your Security Mindset Needs to Follow

VPNs have become a vulnerability that puts organizations at risk of cyberattacks.


Mark Guntrip
Senior Director, Cybersecurity Strategy, Menlo Security
December 23, 2021


Source: denisismagilov via Adobe Stock


When businesses first sent employees to work from home in March 2020 — thinking it'd only be for two weeks — they turned to quick fixes that would enable remote work for large numbers of people as quickly as possible. While these solutions solved the short-term challenge of allowing distributed workforces to connect to a company's network from anywhere, they're now becoming a security vulnerability that is putting organizations at risk of growing cyberattacks.

Now that almost two years have passed and work has fundamentally shifted, with fully or hybrid remote environments here to stay, business and security leaders need solutions that better fit their unique and increasingly complex needs. In fact, a new survey from Menlo Security has found that 75% of organizations are reevaluating their security strategies for remote employees, exemplifying that accommodating remote work is a top priority for the majority of business leaders.

To successfully manage the risks that distributed workforces entail, leaders must shift their mindset away from the hub-and-spoke approach of providing connectivity to the entire network, instead segmenting access by each individual private application, wherever it is deployed, as threats of cyberattacks loom across all industries. As organizations grapple with the added security challenges that remote and hybrid work environments bring, adopting a zero-trust approach will be critical for end-to-end network and endpoint protection.

Move Away From VPNs

Many businesses claim they are confident in their remote access security, yet the survey mentioned above also found that 75% of these organizations are still relying on virtual private networks (VPNs) for controlling remote access to applications. This is a problem. VPNs are an inherently insecure way of doing things, as they open access to everything on a network — meaning that as little as one person falling for a phishing scam could potentially put an entire network at risk of a cyber or ransomware attack. And with employees working from anywhere and everywhere for the foreseeable future, this is a risk that organizations can no longer be willing to take.


On top of the innate risks that VPNs hold, they are also difficult to manage at scale. Instead, business leaders should consider adopting a global cloud security platform that removes the burden of hardware management and offers elastic scalability for remote network access. Solutions that not only provide connectivity to applications but can secure the communication between the end user and the private application will remove potential security blind spots and enable an organization to protect the application and data from misuse.

Adopt a Zero-Trust Approach

While the zero-trust framework is not new, it is gaining steam across the public and private sectors, with the Biden administration encouraging all security leaders to adopt zero-trust-first strategies. According to the survey, more than a third of organizations are already pursuing some form of a zero-trust approach to providing remote access. This growing trend signals that the security industry is beginning to understand that it must move toward solutions that leave nothing to chance by preventing and isolating threats, rather than reacting to them after they strike and potentially cause irreversible damage.

Zero-trust network access provides users with access only to applications and resources that are needed to do their job. Adopting this approach across an entire organization can change your whole security mindset and better protect your organization from attackers by ensuring full confidence in the entire network, from top to bottom — allowing your business to get ahead of modern threats by eliminating them. And while no single solution can provide all components needed for a fully baked zero-trust approach, you can prioritize which elements your organization needs most and build your customized security strategy from there.

As we prepare for the new future of work, one thing is certain: Fully embracing remote work means securing it. The Internet has become the new corporate network, and regulating employee access to private applications is more important now than ever. To best protect organizations moving forward, business leaders need to evolve their thinking from providing connectivity to the entire network to segmenting access by each individual application. They need to invest in solutions that will scale with their business and ensure protection 24/7. By adopting a zero-trust approach appropriate for your business, you will enable seamless, secure access between end users and the applications they are authorized to use, while all other applications are essentially invisible — preventing lateral discovery and closing a backdoor across the network.

The Irish Times on cybersecurity: Taking the threat seriously

All State agencies must finance digital systems and security expertise needed to deal with cyber threats


As the highly critical report on the attack earlier this month from PwC makes clear, the HSE’s cyber defences weren’t remotely fit for purpose, even though many long-standing problems were clearly identified to the service in the past. Photograph: Kacper Pempel/Reuters

 

The long tail – and tale – of the devastating cyberattack waged against the Health Service Executive’s computer services last May continued in recent days as the HSE received a tranche of stolen patient data via the Garda National Cyber Crime Bureau. The information was being stored in the US.

Now, the long task begins of identifying the individuals whose personal information was compromised during an attack that the HSE predicts may ultimately cost the service more than €100 million to address. For everyone affected – and inevitably, that is all of us – the costs are incalculable. An already-overburdened and delayed medical system was dealt a crippling blow. For weeks, patient consultations, diagnoses or treatments were disrupted.

And that’s before adding in the risks to individuals of having some of their most sensitive personal information – not just names, addresses and credit card data, but treatment details – sold on to the dark web, potentially to be exploited for identity theft, financial fraud, or blackmail attempts.

As the highly critical report on the attack earlier this month from PwC makes clear, the HSE’s cyber defences weren’t remotely fit for purpose, even though many long-standing problems were clearly identified to the service in the past.

Weaknesses were multitudinous. Systems were old and creaky, a “frail IT estate” that had suffered from lack of investment over many years, PwC stated. And the HSE lacked the expertise to prevent or respond adequately to an attack.

“It does not possess the required cybersecurity capabilities to protect the operation of the health services and the data they process, from the cyberattacks that all organisations face today,” the report concluded. The latter point is notable: this was not a rare and unexpected event, but a digital commonplace in the 21st century. Not just the HSE, but all State departments and agencies must finance the digital systems, security expertise and staff training needed to deal with cyber threats. We have all learned the painful costs of doing otherwise, a price that continues to mount.

Amazon's Alexa tasked a 10-year-old with a lethal challenge
by Vilius Petkauskas
28 December 2021


The child's mother was furious with the digital assistant nudging her child to stick a metal item into the power socket.

According to Kristin Livdahl, a mother of a 10-year-old child and a writer, her daughter asked Alexa, a digital Amazon Echo assistant, for a challenge to do.

Somewhat ominously, artificial intelligence offered a potentially lethal task for the child.

"The challenge is simple: plug in a phone charger about halfway into a wall outlet, then touch a penny to the exposed prongs," Alexa said and set the timer for 20 minutes to complete the challenge.

The mother explained that she and her daughter were doing physical challenges to warm up, and her 10-year-old asked for more, prompting the lethal suggestion from Amazon's AI.

"It was a good moment to go through internet safety and not trusting things you read without research and verification again. We thought the cesspool of YouTube was what we needed to worry about at this age—with limited internet and social media access—but not the only thing," Livdahl explained in a Tweet.

The activity Alexa suggested is "the penny challenge," a TikTok trend circulating the social network over a year ago. Inserting metal objects in a power socket may lead to a house fire, severe burns, and even death.

Amazon did not reveal what caused its system to recommend such a challenge, but it explained fixing the issue in a statement to the BBC.

"As soon as we became aware of this error, we took swift action to fix it," the company claims.



Online fraud is an ‘epidemic’
by Chris Stokel-Walker
27 December 2021



The latest report by Group-IB highlights the ways scammers operate.

Scams and phishing remain two of the most alarming and dangerous ways that cybercriminals can leverage insight into people’s lives. It’s an indication of just how far it’s risen that Russian cybersecurity firm Group-IB has deemed it an “epidemic of online fraud” – an indication of its pervasiveness and risk to rank and file users.

And its scale is equally concerning to the cybersleuths. More than 14,000 phishing resources were blocked by Group-IB in the first six months of 2021, an indication of how widespread their use and deployment in the online world is. Those phishing resources were hosted on 12,000 unique domains – with around one in five websites hosted on compromised legitimate resources.

That all-encompassing, easily-available scam network is changing the types of people who operate such cons, according to Group-IB. “The popularity of the scam-as-a-service model has led to scams scaling up on a global level and to a lower entry threshold for newbie-scammers with no real skills for conducting scams,” they say.
Scams increasing in popularity

In the first half of 2020, scams accounted for 54% of all cybercrime that Group-IB encountered. That’s risen to 57% in the first half of 2021, based on the ability in part of everyday people to launch their own attacks through scam-as-a-service models, where people buy off-the-shelf tools that enable them to project attacks into the wild without any prior knowledge of coding.

Phishing too has seen an increase in popularity, going from 16% of all cybercrime in the first six months of 2020 to 17.5% of all cybercrime a year later.

One thing that hasn’t changed much is the geographical distribution of from where such phishing attacks are hosted.

The US, Germany and Canada were the top countries hosting phishing websites in H1 2021, according to Group-IB data. Perhaps because of its ubiquity as the de facto reliable gTLD, the United States’s .com accounted for 60% of all phishing sites.

A new scam uncovered


Alongside looking at how scammers have operated in the past, Group-IB tries to identify the latest scams and how they operate. One they’ve recently found targets users in over 90 countries all around the world, including the United States, Canada, South Korea, and Italy. The fraudsters employ the tried and tested technique with fake surveys and giveaways purporting to be from popular brands to steal users’ personal and payment data, with the total number of big-name companies impersonated in the scheme exceeding 120.

Group-IB fears that about 10 million people could be losing about $80 million per month to this scam, according to their estimates.

Fraudsters trap their victims by distributing invitations to partake in a survey, after which the user would allegedly get a prize.

The “branded survey” page takes very long to download because would-be victims find themselves in a long chain of redirects, which scammers use to glean as much information about their session as possible, including the country they’re based in, their time zone, language, IP and browser. The final scam link is customised to a specific user and can be opened only once.

Users are asked to answer questions to receive a prize from a well-known brand and to fill out a form asking for their personal data. The data required usually includes the full name, email, postal address, phone number, bank card data, including expiration date and CVV, says Group-IB – all you need to scam someone.

“Just a couple of years ago, online scams were focused on scale: by indiscriminately targeting users, fraudsters tried to ensure that at least someone would take the bite,” says Dmitriy Tiunkin, Group-IB Digital Risk Protection head, Europe. “Over time, as scam awareness was growing, fewer and fewer people fell prey to such schemes, which made it much more difficult for cybercriminals to make money.” This is just the latest example of a hyper-targeted scam fooling individuals.

Kronos ransomware fallout: Electrolux workers still not receiving full pay

by Edvardas Mikalauskas
29 December 2021


It appears that the aftershock effects of the ransomware attack on Kronos are still felt by real people who are not getting their full paychecks weeks after the incident took place.

Employees at an Electrolux facility in South Carolina claim that they haven’t been paid in full for about two weeks, according to a WSPA 7News report.

The report comes about two weeks after Kronos, a major HR and payroll service provider, suffered a ransomware attack that prevented the company’s clients from accessing staff management and payroll processing services.

According to WSPA 7News, Electrolux North America released a statement on Monday about the Kronos ransomware incident. “Kronos, our time clock supplier, is experiencing a global systems issue and is working to address it as quickly as possible. Upon learning this news, we immediately moved to manually recording employee work hours at the factory to ensure our employees are accurately paid, including overtime,” said the company.

One Electrolux employee told WSPA 7News that she hasn’t received a paycheck for the week of December 13 through 17.

Due to the disruptions caused by the Kronos ransomware attack, teams at the Electrolux facility had to resort to putting down their time clock data on paper. “We had to manually do it on a piece of paper and write everybody’s names down, and what time they came in and what time they left,” another employee told the reporter.

Kronos, the HR company that suffered the ransomware attack, claims that the initial forensic investigation shows the incident affected Kronos Private Cloud, the portion of UKG business where UKG Workforce Central, UKG TeleStaff, Healthcare Extensions, and Banking Scheduling Solutions are deployed.

Other high-profile Kronos clients who rely on services affected by the attack include Tesla, Puma, Sainsbury's, and the City of Cleveland.
Golden age for ransomware gangs

Pundits talk of a ransomware gold rush, with the number of attacks increasing over 90% in the first half of 2021 alone.

The prevalence of ransomware has forced governments to take multilateral action against the threat. It's likely a combined effort allowed to push the infamous REvil and BlackMatter cartels offline and arrest the Cl0p ransomware cartel members.

Gangs, however, either rebrand or form new groups. Most recently, LockBit 2.0 was the most active ransomware group with a whopping list of 203 victims in Q3 of 2021 alone.