Wednesday, February 07, 2024

 

Out on a Limb with Dialectical Materialism

What Can Mechanism, Organicism, Formism, Contextualism and Process Philosophy Teach Marxists?

Orientation

Who cares about philosophy?

When most people hear about philosophy, they think it is:

  • Hopelessly abstract
  • The opposite of concreate reality
  • The opposite of application
  • For talking heads who are otherwise inept and clumsy – the wallflowers at a party
  • It has no impact on daily life unless we consciously apply it
  • It is a philosophical study about lives of old great men, either talking heads or idle dreamers

As we proceed, I hope you will feel differently about philosophy. In my experience, philosophy is one of the most practical subjects to study there is. Why? Because the simplest practical act contains within it assumptions about the nature of reality. Furthermore, a person does not have to have a conscious interest in philosophy in order for that to be operating in their life. Either we choose our philosophy consciously, or it chooses us. If we do not choose it consciously, including the way in which we make meaning, our actions will be out of our control.

I think of philosophy as the skeleton of our thinking process, our infrastructure. If a person has worked out a rough sense of where they stand on the basic philosophical questions, then over time that stance will sink into the plumbing of how they think about any everyday problem. It will seem less and less abstract and closer to everyday life. In other words, the person will see how the choices made in everyday life relate to the abstract philosophical issues. In addition, the individual’s thinking process will be interconnected and more consistent across a wider and wider range of situations. As it stands now most people’s thinking processes are a confused hodge-podge of contradictory platitudes, unexamined assumptions which are often centered around religious belief. But you may say, how do philosophical assumptions get inside the heads of people who have no interest in it?

Every culture must have answers to the fundamental questions regarding the relationship of the group to the larger reality. Part of what makes human life tolerable is the meaning we give to these questions. Now the answers to these big questions have been answered throughout history in various ways. Further, new philosophical questions come into being at different points in history, depending on the general problems a society faces. So I don’t think that philosophical questions are eternal and unanswerable. Over time we develop answers to some questions which are good enough to generate a set of problems for scientists to solve. Cultures that do not develop science answer these questions through mythical stories. Philosophy is not invented voluntarily by smart people.Every individual living in an industrial capitalist society today has at least partly internalized the philosophical thinking and assumptions of Plato and Aristotle because both Protestant and Catholic theorists have drawn from them. Of course, it is possible to challenge their ontology and epistemology but it takes substantial effort.

My claim

My purpose in this article is to argue that dialectical materialism (which I will refer to as DM) is too narrow in the way it understands the history of philosophy. Typically, it divides the schools into idealist or materialist. Through the work of Stephen Pepper and Andrew Reck I will suggest that the history of philosophy can be better grouped into five schools. These schools will do better justice to the variety of what philosophical ontology has to offer.

Ontological Questions

Ontology deals with the fundamental nature of reality. So let’s look at what these philosophical questions are which every philosophical school must deal with:

  • What are we? Are we biological, social or spiritual beings?
  • Where do we come from? the earth or the heavens?
  • Where are we going? Is there an afterlife or do we die in our graves?
  • How is the universe organized? What proportion is designed, improvised, determined or chaotic?
  • What is the relationship between mind and matter? Which is primary and which is derived?
  • Is the universe good, evil or neither?
  • What is the relationship between permanence and change? Which is primary and which is secondary?
  • What is the relationship between determinism and free will? To what extent can our actions be controlled?
  • What is the nature of time? Is it coexistence with space and matter or does it emerge separately?
  • What is the shape of time? Is it cyclical, linear or a spiral?
  • What is the nature of space? Is space an empty container for matter? Is it separate from matter? Or is space a qualitative location for magical correspondences such as the zodiac of astrology?

Epistemological Questions

Epistemology answers the question of how we know things. Epistemological questions include the following:

  • How trustworthy or untrustworthy are our senses in how we know things? Are they direct reflections of the material world (naïve realism)?
  • Are the senses partly accurate and must be refined by reason?
  • How trustworthy or untrustworthy is reason in telling us about what is true?
  • How trustworthy is mathematics (rationality) in describing to us what is true?
  • How trustworthy are our emotions in guiding our understanding of the world?
  • Is there such a psychological process such as intuition and if there is how is it different from the senses, reason, rationality, and emotions?
  • How trustworthy is a revelation (claims to knowledge that are claimed to come from other worlds)?

Our major focus will be on the ontological schools with some reference to epistemology.

Axiology

The field has to do with the nature of values. These values include morals, ethics and beauty. I will not be addressing this topic in this article.

How Many Philosophical Schools are There?

Since I am a Marxist and I studied how Marxists made sense of philosophy, I was taught to divide all philosophical schools into either idealist or materialist. Over the years I have come to see that this grouping was too stark and narrow. Thanks to the work of Stephen Pepper in his book World Hypothesis his division made more sense to me. He divided philosophical schools into:

  • Organicism
  • Contextualism
  • Formism
  • Mechanism

I also found the work of Andrew Reck very helpful. In his book Speculative Philosophy he grouped philosophical schools into:

  • Idealism
  • Materialism
  • Realism
  • Process philosophy

Roughly speaking materialism and mechanism have considerable overlap. The same is true between process philosophy and contextualism. There is more moderate overlap between idealism and organicism but there is more difference than in our first two pair. Realism stands roughly midway between materialism and idealism in Reck’s system. Lastly, formism overlaps with realism.

In the following section I will describe the assumptions of each school. I will also compare the schools to each other. For example, I show that mechanism and organicism will have different answers when applied to how each understands the relationship between individual and society. I will also name the philosophers who go with each school. The assumptions for each school will answer most of the ontological questions at the beginning of this article.

Lastly, all philosophical tendencies don’t fit neatly into the schools listed. Schools of thinking such as rationalism, empiricism and skepticism, pragmaticism, or positivism are mixtures of two or three different schools. Rather than add these and raise further complications, for purposes of learning I wanted not to be overly simplistic (materialism vs idealism) or overly complicated. I suspect there will be some inconsistencies in parts. My intention is to give you a rough and ready map so that you can categorize individual philosophers you might be aware of into their proper categories. Once you become aware of the typical responses of some of these great thinkers you will be in a better position to make up your own mind and group the philosophers into schools rather than treat each as individuals.

Mechanical or Atomistic View

Fundamental assumptions

  • Entities of things exist prior to their relationships (objects are mutable and self-contained atoms).
  • Relations only externally or secondarily define an entity.
  • Differences are prior to commonalities.
  • Boundaries are prior to connections (freedom is the right to be separate).
  • Reductionism is a complex system that can be completely accounted for by analyzing their simple parts. Qualitative relations can be completely understood by quantification.
  • There is no design in nature, neither divine or human (all change is due to either rigid determinism or chance or both.
  • There is no self-reflection within entities (as opposed to an internally generated feedback system).
  • Change is secondary and is not constitutional or necessary. Change is an anomaly or a temporarily disturbance on a more basic state of permanence.
  • Linear or cyclic causality. Initial conditions determine the outcome. The past determines the future. This is as opposed to being pulled in the direction of a future goal as in divine or human teleology.
  • Change eventually leads to a state of equilibrium or homogeneity. This is opposed to change leading to disequilibrium, accumulation, irreversibility and crisis. From this more complex heterogeneous systems may emerge.

Two forms of Mechanism; discrete and Consolidation

In his book World Hypothesis, Stephen Pepper further divides Mechanism into two parts:

  • Discrete
  • Consolidated

Discrete mechanism is ruled by chance.

  • Things are real only if they have a time and place (as opposed to what is real being hidden or sometime in the future) and grounded on primary qualities such as size, shape, motion, solidity, mass (weight) and number. Secondary qualities such as color, texture, smell and sound are not counted
  • Most of the structured features of nature are externally related. These include space from time; every atom from every other atom; every natural law from every other natural law; primary from secondary qualities; names of things from their objects (nominalism).
  • Fields of location are primary
  • Whatever can be located is real.
  • Only particularities exist.
  • Atoms are indestructible and eternal.
  • Time is an infinite one-dimensional manifestation of externally related locations.

In the history of philosophy examples of discrete mechanism are Leucippus, Democritus, Epicurus and Lucretius from the ancient world of Greece and Rome. Gassendi, Galileo, Hobbes and Descartes are representatives from early modern Europe.

Consolidated mechanism is ruled by determinism

The entire world is internally determined, and machine-like. The structure of space and time is completely determined. Historical examples in the history of Western philosophy include Spinoza, Laplace, De La Mettrie, d’Holbach and Helvetius all from the 17th to the 19th centuries.

Each form of mechanism is called a “mechanical materialism” by Marxian dialectical materialists.

Examples of mechanism at work in understanding the relationship between society and the individual

This contrast will be between mechanical materialism and dialectical materialism. Mechanical materialism is the philosophical position of capitalists.

  • Individuals are more than or equal to the sum of social relations.

This is in contrast to the Marxian dialectical materialism which says society is more than the sum of individuals.

  • Individuals or families can exist independently of society as in functional or dysfunctional families or healthy or sick individuals.

Dialectical materialists would say that whatever problems there are within the family or individuals they are ultimately grounded in larger social institutions.

  • Home is the haven from a heartless society.

Dialectical materialism says that, like Martha and the Vandellas, there is nowhere to run. The only haven is building a heartfelt society.

  • The individual’s relation to society is voluntary, accidental and contractual, as in Rousseau’s social contract theory.

For dialectical materialists, individuals’ relation to society, is constitutional, necessary and organic.

  • Society exists as a neutral field in which individuals compete to satisfy needs and pursue happiness.

The opposite of this for dialectical materialists is society as a womb which gives birth to individuals through cooperative relations. Competitive relations internal to society are a product of the last 400 years (Macpherson, The Theory of Possessive Individualism).

  • Social change only partly impacts individual change.

Dialectical materialists say that social change will dramatically change an individual like whether or not they want this.

  • Freedom consists of minimizing external social constraints and maximizing the pursuit of private dreams. Flying “free as a bird”.

What is the opposite of this? It is discovering freedom by acting first within social constraints and then acting on those constraints and expanding them. As Robert Frost said, freedom is moving easily within your harness.

  • Human beings cannot shape history since history is the result of only determinism or chance. Only extraordinary individuals can shape history.

For dialectical materialists human beings can shape history, not just extraordinary individuals. However the shaping is mostly unintended and behind our backs. It is possible to design history in the future.

Organic World View

In DM view, the organic view is connected with idealism. For us, most of the organic view of the world is the opposite of mechanism.

Fundamental assumptions of organicism

  • Relations within a larger whole define entities.

Objects will change as the whole changes:

  • Relations within a larger whole internally define what is an object.
  • Commonalities within a larger whole are more important than differences.
  • Differences have to do with differences in the entity’s functional role within the whole of which it is a part.
  • Connections within a whole are more important than boundaries.

All boundaries are relative and permeable.

  • Anti-reductionism – complex systems cannot be completely understood in terms of their parts; qualitative relations cannot be completely understood through quantification.
  • There is design in nature. There is a hierarchy of wholes with the supreme spirit at the top.
  • Entities grow in self-reflection. They develop self-regulating feedback systems.
  • Change of an entity is inevitable and moving towards the self-development of the whole universe
  • Reciprocal causality. All entities reciprocally affect each other so that what was once a cause is now an effect. It is the future telos or striving that is the final cause.
  • Change inevitably leads to increased differentiation or heterogeneity, increasing expansion and integration with other entities.

Organic worldviews on truth, conflict and evil

  • Truth lies in development.

Unlike the mechanist, truth is not to be found in local space and present time.

It is found in ever-widening connections between entities which will occur in some future time.

  • Appearances are secondary. What counts is an ever-unfolding unity. This unity is in the process of becoming which is deeper than appearances and is largely hidden.
  • The importance of stages. The present state of entities is only a moment of their true identity, which unfolds over time.
  • Conflict is secondary. They are understood as either inconsequential or illusions.
  • Evil is a product of social or psychological problems. It not ontologically real.

Examples in the history of western philosophy include Schelling, Hegel, Green, Bradley, Bosanquet and Royce.

Contextualism

Contextualism shares with mechanism a materialist outlook, but it is not the reductionist mechanical materialism. In many ways contextualism is the opposite of organicism and it has most in common with process philosophy which I will cover shortly.

Fundamental assumptions of contextualism

  • Entities have no essence independent of the situation or context in which they are embedded.

These contexts are not necessarily wholes or systems (in contrast to the organicist view).

  • The uniqueness of each context is more valuable to understand than the commonalities between situations
  • Anti-reductionism. Elementary analysis can be distortive of the richness of the context
  • There will always be elements in the universe which are recalcitrant and will resist organization and integration (unlike the organicist).
  • Anti-foundationalist. There is no top or bottom in the universe. The search for either an ultimate material building block (mechanism) or a supreme force at the top (organicism) is fruitless.
  • Change is primary and structure is secondary. However, change is not preprogramed in a particular direction as it is in organicism.
  • Novel events are constantly coming into being that are unpredictable relative to previous structures.
  • Improvisation in nature produces more complex levels but these levels are not designed.
  • Time is part of the creative process in nature

Time is much more than a tracker of events. Time is part of the events themselves and changes them.

  • Reciprocal causality. All contexts reciprocally determine others, but as material, formal or efficient causes. Unlike organicism there are no final causes.
  • Truth is present in every local context or situation.

This is opposed to the need to derive natural laws from sensuous events (mechanism).

Neither is truth an end point in development as in organicism.

  • Truth lies in its ultimate utility, as successful functioning. Truth is, as William James says, in its consequences, in what works.

Most of the contextualism school comes out of the Yankeedom pragmatists, William James, John Dewey, George Herbert Mead and to some extent, Charles Sanders Peirce.

Realism/Formism

This is the trickiest category of all the schools of philosophy. First, because it is easy to confuse with Organism or Idealism. Secondly, because there is an ontological realism which I will discuss also and an epistemological realism.

Ontological realism

There is an objective world of universals like Platonic forms, typologies, archetypes and templates which exist transcendentally to either the material world or the human mind that seeks to grasp them. Universals can be love, beauty, or truth.

This issue emerged in medieval times over the question of the relationship between the universal and particular things. There were three possible positions:

  • Nominalism – only particular things are real. Universals such as fathers or mothers are not as real as sensually detected objects.
  • Conceptualism – universals exist, but only as conceptions in the human mind.

Their being is in human mentality. In the natural world there are only individual things.

  • Realism – universals have existence beyond particular things or mental constructions of those things. Universals are beyond matter and human minds. They are archetypes or like Plato’s forms.

The main problem of universals is how to connect the particular to the general. Another problem is the relationship between external objects in nature and mental objects. This included the relationship between sense data, perception, representation and ideas. Another problem is the relationship between the mind and the body; that is between mental states and physiological processes.

In the history of philosophy in the ancient world, Plato and St. Augustine are good examples. In the medieval world, Duns Scotus defends realism against nominalism.

Closer to the present, Charles Sanders Peirce was a realist.

Fundamentalist formism or realism assumptions

  • What is the relationship between things and form? Form or types exist prior to things.
  • What is the relationship between commonalities and differences? Commonalities matter more.
  • What is the connection between change and structure? Structure matters more. Change comes out of structure. Change is a sign of imperfection?
  • What matters is what is eternal. Time is atemporal (unlike Organicists).
  • There is design in nature, but it happens once. This is unlike the Organicists for which design is an ongoing process in nature.
  • There are levels in reality, but the levels are there from the beginning. They don’t unfold (Organicist) or emerge (process philosophy).
  • Ordering of the levels: descend from the top, down.
  • What is the place of self-reflection? Self-reflection is there from the beginning. It is not an unfolding or an emergence.
  • Type of causality – final causes, due to purpose at the beginning.
  • What is the relationship between appearance and reality? Appearance as surfaces which create illusions (Plato). Reality is invisible, prior to and behind appearances.
  • How do we make sense of conflicts? Conflicts are not part of nature as they are with the Contextualists. They are to be explained away as due to ignorance or wrong information. The ultimate reality has no conflicts.
  • Epistemological foundations are grounded in externalities, eternal forms (Plato) or Aristotle’s unmoved mover.
  • What is the realist theory of truth? Truth is externally found in mathematical equations, geometry, maps, diagrams and formulas. This is opposite to the contextual theory of truth. The latter is operational and is manifested in successful functioning or in concrete consequences.

Epistemological realism

This is directed mostly at Organicists either objective idealists like Hegel or various subjective idealists like Kant or Fichte. Epistemological realism says there is an independent objective world independent from the mind that knows it. When cognition relates knowing minds to objects known or knowable, these objects will always have independence of any mind, human or divine.

Epistemological realism comes close to materialism or mechanism because it implies:

  • The independence of biophysical nature.
  • The mind does not exist as a substance but rather as a function of the physical organism.

The philosophers who were tenacious examples of epistemological realism were all in the 20th century and included GE Moore; RB Perry, A. Lovejoy; Santayana and Strong.

Process Philosophy

Evolution

In science, the seventeenth century had been the century of physics and astronomy. In the eighteenth century thanks to Lyell, there was the discovery through geology of deep time. With the invention of the microscope, we learned about minuscule organisms. When Darwin began his studies when on the voyage of the Beagle we learned of the vast variety of organisms. But of course, Darwin went much further, first in his discovery of adaptation and sexual selection. Then in 1871 with his book The Descent of Man, the relationship between humanity and the rest of nature was posed without the need for a “Grand Creator” who divinely intervened.

Creativity in time

In the history of philosophy neither mechanical materialists, nor organicists or realists took time seriously. Along with space, it was a container for natural or social events. Marx and Engels were among the first to suggest that human history was a process of class struggle, rather that the frozen events like congresses or wars. Pragmatists in the late 19th century like Charles Sanders Peirce and Chauncey Wright sought to think not just about quantitative change within organic nature but qualitative change that occurred in large scale relationships between matter (the inorganic), life (the organic) and the human mind. Peirce writes that evolution displays three types:

  • Tychism – evolution of change
  • Anancasm – mechanical necessity
  • Agapism – evolution of creative love

It was Henri Bergson who emphasized that “creative evolution” was a never ending process and that static events were temporary thick moments of an effervescence  movement the flowed between matter, life and mind.

Immanent vs emergent evolution

In the philosophy of Schelling and Hegel, organicists had their answer. The lower levels of nature were immanent in the higher levels. What happened at the lower levels unfolded from higher forms. Higher forms descended into the lower and brought them up. In the 20th century Teilhard de Chardin and Sri Aurobindo in India continued this tradition.

By what if Bergson was right about creativity of time? Does that mean that instead of evolution being immanent, evolution was emergent? What if the levels of nature emerged from lower levels and there was real novelty in nature? This was the road taken by George Lewes in the mid-19th century and followed up on by British philosopher comparative psychologist C. Lloyd Morgan and by the American philosopher Roy Wood Sellars and to a lesser extent by John Dewey. In the field of social psychology George Herbert Mead showed how society was the next emergent property beyond life and matter.

Process theology

Many see the grandest synthesis of process philosophy in the work of Alfred North Whitehead in his great book Process and RealityWhitehead did not want to abandon process philosophy to materialists and insisted that God can be seen as a process rather than as a being. Charles Hartshorne learned from Whitehead and added some twists of his own. David Ray Griffin worked to sharpen the work of Hartshorne. Process theologists wanted to unify nature through a kind of panpsychism, without any supernaturalism.

Fundamental assumptions and endeavors of process philosophy

Despite the differences between theological and secular process philosophy we can still identify many principles that unite them:

  • Movement and change is the primary reality. It is ongoing independently of human intentions. Structure or form is a derivative of change and not primary as it is with the mechanists.
  • It strives to articulate the conditions in which change takes place.

To what extent is it the result of necessity, chance or design?

  • It strives to develop a typology of change distinguishing qualitative from quantitative change and distinguishing transitions from crisis.
  • It strives to understand the shape of change whether that change is cyclic, linear, non-linear or a spiral.

Are changes oscillations of a primary statis state? Are changes irreversible or reversible?

  • To what extent does change accumulate and have consequences?

Process philosophy strives to understand the relationship to time, the past, present and future.

  • It strives to understand the levels of change. Process philosophers involve themselves in understanding the relationship between matter, life, mind and society.
  • It strives to understand the value of change.

Is change inherently good, progressive and negentropic? Or is change degenerative, and entropic? Is change necessary?

With which other school of philosophy does process philosophy have most in common?

Process philosophy shares most in common with contextualism.

  • There are no essences independent of contexts and situations
  • Anti-reductionism – there are levels of complexity in nature.
  • There are recalcitrant elements in nature which resist organization.
  • Anti-foundationalism – change is infinite in space and time.

There is no bottom or top where change ceases.

  • Emergence of novel events are constantly happening in the universe.
  • Nature is self-regulating through improvisation. Nature creates and recreates herself.
  • Time and timing is a constitutional element in this improvisation.

What Can Dialectical Materialism Learn from Mechanism, Organicism, Formism, Contextualism and Process Philosophy?

Mechanism

In trying to integrate DM to the five schools, it’s best to start with mechanism because mechanism starts from the material world, nature. It dismisses any spiritual essences or interventions. At the same time, DM departs from mechanism  because mechanism is reductionist. In contrast, DM shares with contextualists and process philosophy a sense of emergent levels in nature. Furthermore, mechanism lacks a sense of self-reflectiveness that characterizes organicism and contextualism. DM shares with mechanism the conviction that what drives natural evolution is necessity and chance. What mechanism misses is that at the level of humanity there is design in nature in that human social plans that can change nature. Lastly mechanism’s sense of matter is that it is dead and externally driven. In DM, as for La Mettrie, matter is dynamic and self-organizing.

Organicism

DM is directly opposed to organicism in its point of departure. Organicism starts with a spiritual whole whether the whole is of Schelling or Hegel. DM begins with matter in motion.  It agrees with organicism that there are levels in nature, but it sees these levels as emergent processes, driven from the bottom to the top. Organicism understands levels in nature as unfolding and moving from top to bottom and back to the top. DM agrees with organicism that self-reflection and internality are an important part of nature. Yet, organicists assume self-reflection is built into the cosmos as a whole, right from the beginning. For DM self-reflection is an emergent process which occurs with the rise of social complexity. Self-reflection is not there at the beginning. DM agrees with organicism that internal relations precede things. However, internal relations only apply at certain levels of complexity. Primitive matter does not have internal relations. It is driven by external relations such as natural selection and chance variations. We agree with organicist Hegel that conflict is the mother of all change. However, Hegel’s conflict is too neat and pretty and lacks the “out of control” dimension when conflict is generated outside the system.

Formism/Realism

DM has the least in common with formism for many reasons. We don’t think much of Plato who is probably the most well-known Formist. Like organicists, Formists start with a spiritual essence (Plato’s eternal forms) but unlike organicists Formism lacks a developmental direction that organicists share with DM. Also, unlike organicists time is unimportant to Formists, while it is essential to emergent nature for DM. Formists are opposite to DM in that conflict and change are indicators that something is wrong. In DM both conflict and change are more important that stability or types. We agree with Formists that appearances should not be taken as given. For us, the senses can be deceptive and should not be taken for granted. However for Formists, appearances never tell the truth because they depart from eternal forms. For us, sometimes the senses, corrected by reason are trustworthy. We agree with Formists that structures are important, but for us structures are not transcendental, eternal forms. They are a necessary part of nature but they change, disintegrate and reform.

Contextualism

DM has a great deal in common with contextualism. We appreciate their perspective on situational change, conflicts as foundational in nature and emergence as a property of levels in nature. We applaud its insistence that appearances matter but they often understate the important of structures underneath appearances. DMs are less militant that there are no foundations in nature. Though foundations today keep changing (the nature of subatomic particles) that doesn’t mean it will always be that way.  Our main problem with contextualism is that it comes out of a liberal understanding of society. The pragmatists – whether James, Dewey and to a lesser extent Peirce and Mead – see the individual as the basic unit. This applies to its theory of truth – practice and consequences. For DM truth for humans is practice, but social practice. Individual practice is not the test of truth for science. Individuals are far too untrustworthy to measure the truth of something. It is the social practice of science which is a much more reliable test.

Process philosophy

Process philosophy can be broken down into types:

  • The naturalistic process philosophy of Heraclitus, Lloyd Morgan and Roy Wood Sellars.
  • The process theology of Samuel Alexander, Teilhard de Chardin, Whitehead, Hartshorne and David Ray Griffin

DM has little in common with Chardin’s God or Whitehead’s eternal objects. We would take issue with Hartshorne or David Ray Griffin’s argument that the internality of nature goes very far back. Rather, psyche is emergent in complex human life.  However, some of the concepts of Samuel Alexander can be worked into a dialectical framework. For example, Alexander’s slogan “deity is an effort not an accomplishment” is a powerful statement about what matters most is movement rather than things. Alexander’s God is the material world in its totality. This makes Alexander a pantheist god. Furthermore, Chardin’s concept of a noosphere surrounding the earth speaks to the globalization of society and a planetary communist society in the future. I still find Chardin’s description of the growth of the noosphere as breathtaking now as it was to me 50 years ago.

Process philosophy has levels in nature, usually matter, life and mind. DM claims  that levels of nature are matter, life (biology) and society, not mind.

Mind is the emergent result of societies that grow to become complex. In addition, process philosophy has no primary place of conflict in its philosophy. Unlike Hegel and Marx, in which conflict is the driver of evolution, for process philosophy if conflict exists at all in nature it is not given a primary place. As Marxists evil for us has no ontological status. Rather it is a derivative of social life under class conditions. For theological process philosophy, evil has an ontological place though their evil has nothing to do with any fundamentalist devil. DM stress the importance of time, not just in philosophy, but in social life such as the preconditions for capitalism and socialism. Both dialectical materialism and process philosophy see nature as self-regularity and immanent.

What’s wrong with dialectical materialism

DM has two forms of idealism – the objective idealism of Plato, Schelling and Hegel and the subjective idealism of Kant and Fichte. However, it makes no distinction between Formists like Plato and Organicists like Hegel and Schelling. Secondly, while the distinction between mechanical materialism and dialectical materialism is good, the difference between discrete and mechanical materialism is not clear enough. Marx’s dissertation of a comparative study between Democritus and Epicurus should have been followed up on. It is my hope that Marxists open up their framework of philosophy to include six types rather than two or three.

Please see the table on our website for a summary of the six schools at the end of the article.

Six Schools of Philosophy (Pepper and Reck)


Bruce Lerro has taught for 25 years as an adjunct college professor of psychology at Golden Gate University, Dominican University and Diablo Valley College in the San Francisco Bay Area. He has applied a Vygotskian socio-historical perspective to his three books found on Amazon. He is a co-founder, organizer and writer for Socialist Planning Beyond Capitalism. Read other articles by Bruce, or visit Bruce's website.

 

James Smith Cree Nation tragedy ‘could have been avoided’ says AFN national chief


The national chief of the Assembly of First Nations says the lack of First Nations policing and other justice services compounded the tragedy on James Smith Cree Nation back in 2022.

“This tragedy is a systemic failure of the police and the justice system,” Cindy Woodhouse of the Assembly of First Nations said at a news conference in Saskatoon on Thursday. “All the evidence presented throughout the [inquest] further demonstrate that if a First Nations police service had been equitably funded in the James Smith Cree Nation, this tragedy could have been avoided.”

Myles Sanderson, 32, killed 11 people and injured 17 others in James Smith and in Weldon on Sept. 4, 2022. Sanderson, who also killed his brother, died in police custody a few days after the rampage.

For the past two weeks, a six-member jury learned the details of what happened that day, including Sanderson’s time in prison and relationship with his former partner and family.

The jury and coroner made 29 recommendations, including one for the First Nation to establish a local police force.

The inquest heard that the Melfort RCMP detachment, 50 km away from James Smith, first received a report of a stabbing at 5:40 a.m. on the day of the attacks. Officers arrived at 6:18 a.m.

Since the stabbing rampage, leadership in James Smith Cree Nation has pushed for a local police force to be organized. Prime Minister Justin Trudeau promised in 2020 his Liberal government would bring forward a new First Nations policing law.

Woodhouse said the legislation remains stalled.

“We need to get to a table and start talking … right now we’re not,” she said.

Former public safety minister Marco Mendicino had said he would work around the clock to get the legislation tabled in the fall 2022, after the massacre, but later walked back the promise. Woodhouse said she has met with current Public Safety Minister Dominic LeBlanc, but there’s been no movement on the file.

Jurisdiction and whether it should be the provinces or First Nations, remains the main point of contention, Woodhouse said at a news conference with chiefs from Saskatchewan.

Public Safety Canada did not provide a comment to the Canadian Press on Thursday.

“We are spinning our wheels over and over and over, and nothing is happening,” said Chief Wally Burns of James Smith Band, one of three communities that make up the First Nation.

“This is where we have to stop it.”

He said there was a lot of conversation with federal counterparts about First Nations-led policing following the killings. James Smith need boots on the ground soon, he said.

The national chief said she’s looking for $3.6 billion in the March federal budget to begin addressing some of the policing issues on First Nations.

Leadership in communities with Indigenous-led policing have long been raising concerns about chronic underfunding. As of October, there were 36 Indigenous police services across the country. Five are in Western Canada.

They are funded through the First Nations and Inuit Policing Program, which launched in 1991. In its expense-sharing model, Ottawa pays 52 per cent of the costs and the provinces or territories pay 48 per cent.

Last year, the Indigenous Police Chiefs of Ontario and the Quebec Association of First Nation and Inuit Police Directors filed separate human rights complaints against the federal government alleging systemic discrimination because of underfunding.

With files from Kelly Geraldine Malone – the Canadian Press

CANADA

Heated debate on clean drinking water legislation leads to accusations of stereotyping




During a debate in the House of Commons Saskatoon Conservative MP Kevin Waugh said tensions were high in First Nations communities who do not have clean drinking water and remain under a boil water advisory.

“The previous Conservative government left eight and a half years ago and there are still over 100 water advisories on First Nations,” he said.

“In my home province of Saskatchewan, I have seen reserves burn down water treatment plants because the Liberal government has done little or nothing.”

The comments were made during a debate on Bill C-61, also known as the First Nations Clean Water Act, on Monday.

The Liberal Minister of Indigenous Services took issue with Waugh’s comments, made by a Saskatchewan Conservative MP during a debate on the government’s new First Nations water legislation, accusing him of negative “stereotyping.”

“Well the implication that people would burn water treatment plants out of spite, out of anger at the government, out of a sense of wanton destruction – I think came through loud and clear in his comments,” Patty Hajdu said outside the House of Commons on Tuesday.

“I will just say that we see acts of arson in non-Indigenous communities as well. So, there is a stereotype that somehow Indigenous people don’t take care of the equipment or the housing or the community infrastructure and that is a long standing very harmful and hurtful stereotype.”

Waugh later added, “The other thing is that there needs to be education provided for people on reserve to operate these water treatment plants, which is part of the problem we have seen with the government over the last eight and a half years.”

Ending off the heated exchange, Hajdu accused the Conservative MP of using the debate to further historical negative stereotypes of First Nations people.

“Trust a Conservative member to blame First Nations people for burning down their own water treatment plants and for not being smart enough to be able to understand how to operate those plants,” she said

“That is the kind of paternalism that led to 105 long-term boil water advisories. They were just not worth investing in, I guess.”

The Liberals have faced a lot of criticism for failing to deliver on a 2015 commitment to end all long-term drinking water advisories on First Nations by March 2021. Access to clean drinking water remains an issue for many communities. According to the Indigenous Services Canada website, there were 28 long-term drinking water advisories in place on First Nations as of Jan. 19 of this year and five of these were in Saskatchewan.

Bill C-61 was introduced just before Christmas with a stated intent to protect water sources, create minimum drinking water standards and provide sustainable funding for water quality on First Nations.

The clean drinking water legislation currently sits at second reading in the House of Commons.

Media reports show there were two water treatment plants destroyed by fires on First Nations in Saskatchewan in recent years.

One in Carry the Kettle Nakoda Nation in 2019 and the other in Piapot First Nation in 2018. The causes of the fires were undetermined in earlier media reports.

APTN News reached out to Kevin Waugh’s office for clarification on his comments in the House of Commons on Monday but did not hear back by press time.

 

NDP MP says there are solutions to homelessness crisis but feds ignoring them





The number of people living in shelters and on the streets has reached an all time high and encampments can be seen in every city and town across the country.  It’s become a crisis in the City of Edmonton and dominated headlines lately.

Blake Desjarlais is Métis Cree and the NDP MP for Edmonton, Alta. He said there are solutions to the problem including bringing back the National Housing Strategy, which was cancelled in 1995 by the Paul Martin Liberal government, would make a significant difference for those living on low income.

“The outcome of that was to begin to see the private market deal completely and solely as the only actor in the housing market, this is the problem that we’re facing in Canada today,” he told Nation to Nation host Annette Francis.

Studies have shown that Indigenous people are 11 times more likely to be unhoused and some suggest racism, historic trauma and colonialism are direct causes.

According to Desjarlais, Canada’s history is one of displacement for Indigenous people and this has direct impacts today.

“When I was in my community of Edmonton, I spoke to people, residential school survivors living in tents,” he said. “I spoke to people who are Sixties scoop survivors of CFS [child and family services] and they were young children out there, because they were dropped off on the street because the child family services system we have in this country is deplorable.”

I AM PROUD TO HAVE HIM AS MY MP


Mining in Ontario

A surge of mining claims in northern Ontario has left some First Nations scrambling to keep up. The Chiefs of Ontario are now asking the province for a one-year moratorium.

Grand Council Chief Reg Niganobe, of the Anishinabek Nation which represents 39 First Nations, says the uptick in claims is due to the online application process.

“This was a concern that had come up already, they made the move anyways and here we are now, First Nations of course are being inundated with so many claims now,” he said.

Niganobe says a pause would help First Nations get back on track and deal with the issue but there’s still many questions for the provincial and federal governments.

“A lot of it is, are the First Nations being consulted on these claims, how the process works, and are First Nations being included in land ownership in these regards,” said Niganobe.

Saskatchewan inquest

parole board
Tobacco sits at the base of each photo of the victims of the James Smith Cree Nation and Welford attack. Photo: Rachel May/APTN.

An inquest into the mass stabbing in James Smith Cree Nation in Saskatchewan wrapped up this week. In September 2022, the community was left in a state of shock after Myles Sanderson killed 11 people and injured 17. Sanderson had breached his parole conditions repeatedly and was considered unlawfully at large when the incidents occurred. He had a lengthy criminal record, including multiple violent offences.

The jury made14 recommendations and the coroner made 15, including better collaboration between James Smith Cree Nation and RCMP and more supports for offenders after they are released into a community.

APTN reporter Rachel May has been covering the inquest for the past two weeks in Melfort, Saskatchewan.

She tells Nation to Nation it was an emotional inquest for all involved.

“It’s been a lot to hear. It’s been hard to hear jury members, family members, community members,” she said. “Everyone affected by the tragedy has heard details that they won’t be able to forget. We’ve seen tears, we’ve seen people break down in the hallways.

“It’s been a very emotional journey, but they also are saying that if the deaths of their family members can bring justice for other people who may have experienced similar deaths in their family, or prevent similar deaths in the future from happening, then their deaths aren’t in vain.”


 

Coalition calls for charges to be dropped against journalist in Edmonton


Several journalism organizations are calling on Crown prosecutors in Edmonton to drop charges against Brandi Morin, an Indigenous journalist who was charged in early January as police were dismantling a homeless encampment.

“Let me be blunt,” said Brent Jolly, president of the Canadian Association of Journalists (CAJ), at a news conference on Jan. 29, “based on all evidence, Brandi was targeted and singled out for doing her job as a journalist. Brandi’s arrest makes an absolute mockery of the right to freedom of the press and the ability to report on the activities of taxpayer-funded law enforcement agencies.

“This entire situation is an abomination, particularly as it relates to the important pursuits of reconciliation and justice. It must be corrected now.”

On Jan. 10, Edmonton police arrested three people, including Morin, who was there covering the raid.

Morin said she identified herself as a reporter to police – yet she was arrested and handcuffed.

In a video posted on social media on Jan. 30, Morin updated her day.

“I am headed to Edmonton police headquarters,” she said in the video. “I have to show up to be fingerprinted, mug-shotted and basically criminalized. This is really solidifying, I’m being criminalized for doing my job – holding the police to account.”


The coalition fighting for the charges to be dropped is comprised of the CAJ, the Committee to Protect Journalists (CPJ), Reporters Without Borders, the Indigenous Journalists Association, the Coalition for Women in Journalism, Journalists for Human Rights, PEN Canada and Amnesty International.

“We’re very concerned by the behaviour of the Edmonton Police toward Brandi Morin,” said Katherine Jacobsen, program coordinator with the CPJ, at the news conference. “Local law enforcement’s decision to press charges against her despite the evidence that she was not in violation of Canadian law at the time of her arrest. Our research shows that arresting reporters serves as a blunt form of censorship.

“A journalist in handcuffs cannot get their story out. Beyond an initial detention, prosecuting reporters creates a harmful chilling effect and serves as a form of intimidation for their peers.”

Morin was later released on a promise to appear in court in February.

 

Manulife-Loblaw debacle a 'teachable moment' in board communication: prof

An expert in corporate governance says the cancelled prescription coverage deal between Manulife and Loblaw is a “teachable moment” when it comes to communication between the between the C suite and the corporate board.

Last month, Manulife announced that Loblaw-owned pharmacies and Shoppers Drug Mart would “primarily” be the ones serving its prescription specialty drug programs. It later backed off the plan following criticism from the public and government.

Richard Leblanc, professor of governance, law and ethics at York University, said the developments likely represent a situation where management was making decisions without discussing them with the board.

“This was, in my view, a teachable moment that if in doubt, go to the board and just get a workout by a second set of eyes,” he told BNN Bloomberg in a television interview.

“Likely if it had gone to the board, management would have been instructed to stand down or to withdraw.”

As grocery stores face pressure around competition, Leblanc said big external partnerships should have people at the very top of a company examining them. 

“We have a minister that is breathing down the neck of grocery companies and you do not want to make sudden moves without going to the board and getting cross examined,” he said.

“Likely if it had gone to the board or did go to the board, you'd have individual directors saying: ‘Well, hang on a second here, the minister wants more competition. Isn't this the complete opposite of what the minister wants?’”

Prior to the pandemic, Leblanc said management could conduct minor transactions without board awareness, but now it’s best practice to include the board in all minor deals, even if there are no financial stakes.

“The board gets a kick at the can when it comes to transactions or actions or strategies by management that have the potential for stakeholder consultation, stakeholder engagement,” he said.

“The board wants to see that the Ts are crossed and the Is are dotted.”

With files from The Canadian Press

 

Real estate commission lawsuit expands across Canada

A lawsuit alleging that the real estate brokerage industry inflates commission fees has been expanded to include all of Canada and an expert says it could bring big changes to the housing market.

The class action suit, filed in federal court last month, names 72 different regional real estate boards, 10 real estate franchisors and eight real estate brokerages as defendants.

“The class action is quite substantial and it’s pretty huge,” Walter Melanson, co-founder and market analyst at PropertyGuys.com, told BNN Bloomberg in a Monday interview.

The lawsuit comes after an original suit was filed in federal court in September on behalf of home-sellers in the Greater Toronto Area against the Toronto Regional Real Estate Board (TRREB).

None of the allegations have been proven in court.

The latest price-fixing suit alleges that an unwritten arrangement known as the “buyer brokerage commission rule,” which has become the norm for many residential real estate transactions, violates competition laws.

When a home sale closes, the seller typically pays a broker commission fee, which is a percentage of the entire sale amount. The fee is normally then split between the representatives of the seller and the buyer, and is customarily shared evenly.

This was the case with Milton resident Kevin McFall, the named plaintiff in the class action suit. In the court documents, McFall alleges he sold his home in May and paid a five per cent commission on the sale, half of which went to the buyer brokerage.

The suit claims that this system incentivizes buyer brokerages to direct their clients away from sellers offering lower commission fees, artificially inflating them over time.

“We're talking about rules that drive policies and policies that drive behaviours and behaviours that drive outcomes,” Melanson explained.


Case follows Missouri court decision

The Canadian class action comes on the heels of a similar case in the U.S.

In a precedent-setting October decision, a Missouri court handed down a guilty verdict in a price-fixing lawsuit brought against major U.S. real estate players including the National Association of Realtors and RE/MAX.

The plaintiffs in that case were awarded US$1.8 billion in damages.

“When it comes to Canada, it's the same types of allegations,” Melanson said.

“The lawyers behind this class action are saying that certain rules prevent competition in the buyer brokerage industry, which lead to falsely inflating real estate commissions, so that's really what the focus is.”


Allegations 'without merit': CREA

The Canada-wide class action suit claims that the Canadian Real Estate Association (CREA) helped brokerages facilitate the alleged price-fixing scheme.

The organization says the allegations are “without merit.”

“(CREA) will continue to vigorously defend against these claims,” CREA said in a statement to BNN Bloomberg.

The association claims its listing system are “efficient and effective cooperative marketplaces that bring together realtors acting on behalf of Canadian home sellers and buyers, and are both pro-competitive and pro-consumer.”


Potential impacts

After the Missouri court decision, Melanson said “copy cat” class action suits have been filed across 11 U.S. states, with the potential to exceed US$100 billion in damages.

Decisions in U.S. courts will likely influence the behaviour of realtors in Canada, Melanson said, noting that many brokerages are already changing their commission rules to de-risk their businesses in the long term.

“It really depends what the folks that are involved in the American suits want to do here in Canada, but we hope that any change is good for consumers,” Melanson said.

He noted that some analysts have estimated that real estate commissions in Canada could come down as much as 30 per cent as a result of the legal action.

“Those are the types of things we'd love to see in the market,” Melanson said.


 

Canada’s housing target falls 1.5 million units short, CIBC says

The Canadian government is underestimating the number of new homes needed to address a spiraling affordability crisis by about 1.5 million units, according to Canadian Imperial Bank of Commerce research.

While Canada’s national housing agency says the country needs to add 3.5 million extra units by 2030 to make shelter affordable, the true number is actually about 5 million additional homes, CIBC economist Benjamin Tal wrote in a report Tuesday. Tal traced the problem to population figures he says don’t adequately count non-permanent residents.

Prime Minister Justin Trudeau’s government is grappling with a nationwide surge in housing costs that political rivals have seized upon for attacks. While the government has tried to make up for years of underbuilding with a raft of policies to boost supply, these have yet to have a meaningful impact on the market. That’s turned attention to how the government’s attempt to drive economic growth by boosting immigration has further knocked supply and demand out of balance.

High interest rates and a slowing economy are further challenging the government’s efforts to boost supply. In December, the total value of building permits in Canada plunged 14 per cent from a month earlier, reaching the lowest monthly level in more than three years, Statistics Canada reported Tuesday. The total value of residential permits fell 17.9 per cent, due largely to a significant drop in multi-unit permit construction intentions.

Much of Canada’s recent population growth has come through non-permanent resident programs — foreign students and temporary workers — which the federal government did not cap and were mainly driven by demand from educational institutions and employers. The Trudeau government’s latest move was to introduce a cap on the number of foreign students.

But CIBC’s Tal says that even if that cap works as intended, growth in other types of non-permanent residents would still ensure about two per cent annualized population growth, or 6 million new people over the next seven years. That kind of growth coming on top of the already-bigger than anticipated population means Canada will need to build considerably more housing than the government thought, Tal said.

“There are no credible forecasts, targets, or capacity plans across governments for non-permanent residents — the population which accounts for the vast majority of the planning shortfall. That must change,” he wrote. “Meaningful forecasting, targets, and integrated planning must be conducted for all permanent and temporary visa approvals to be meaningful.”

In an interview with Bloomberg News, Immigration Minister Marc Miller acknowledged the recent migration surprises have immediate public policy implications, and agreed the government “could do a better job of dealing with the aggregate numbers so people know what they’re solving for.”

Still, he pushed back on suggestions that more predictable population forecasts would have resulted in matching investments in housing and social services from provinces and cities. 

“Let’s not fool ourselves in thinking that even if we were to project out for 10 years, that people would automatically adjust, because people get elected and unelected based on their ability to fulfill promises to the people that got them there,” he said. “They sometimes get elected on cuts.”