Anarchism and the Myth of the Primitive: Godwin and Kropotkin
Samuel Clark
Draft: for final version, see Studies in Social and Political Thought 15(2008): 6-25
Anarchists are commonly supposed to hold deeply optimistic views about human
nature, and to be nostalgic for ‘primitive’ (as opposed to ‘civilised’) societies. I shall
argue here that these claims are false. It is worth doing so, both as a recovery of some
interesting thought from misrepresentation, and because a precise account of
primitivism will be useful in other contexts.
‘Traditionally, anarchists are seen to possess an optimistic conception of
human nature, an optimism essential to the success of their vision of a stateless
society.’2
According to James Joll, ‘The fundamental idea that man is by nature good
and that it is institutions that corrupt him remains the basis of all anarchist thought.’3
For him, anarchists share the mental pathology of heretical Christians who demand
and expect ‘a return to the Golden Age of the Garden of Eden before the Fall’4
. Roger
Scruton claims that ‘typical anarchist beliefs’ include that ‘men are benign by nature
and corrupted by government’5
. Irving Horowitz, that ‘Anarchism has as its
theoretical underpinning an idealization of natural man in contrast and in oppostion to
civilized man … What is offered is a belief in “natural man” as more fundamental and
historically prior to “political man”.’6
Norman Barry, that ‘Communitarian [as
opposed to libertarian] anarchism depends upon an optimistic view of human nature
as essentially benign and cooperative.’7
These examples could easily be continued.
They impute one or both of two claims to anarchists: that they believe, first, in a pure
and good human nature which is distorted or masked by current circumstances;
second, in a long-lost golden age. In sections 1 and 2 below I set out these claims in
2
more detail, and then show in each case that they do not apply to two representative
anarchists, William Godwin and Peter Kropotkin.
Claims that anarchists are primitivists have often been used to ground
criticism. Robert Dahl, for instance, offers as ‘a critique of anarchism’ the thought
that ‘While some romantic anarchists may imagine our returning to the tiny
autonomous groups of some preliterate societies, short of a cataclysm that no sane
person wants, a return to the infancy of the species looks to be impossible or, if not
impossible, highly undesirable.’8
Benjamin Barber attacks anarchists because ‘their
view of actual men is wildly romanticized. Hunger, greed, ambition, avarice, the will
to power, to glory, to honour, and to security which have played some role in all
traditional ethnologies find no place in the anarchist portrait of man’9
. Barber directs
this attack specifically against twentieth-century American anarchists like Abbie
Hoffman, but is explicit that he believes the tradition from Godwin onwards to be
implicated in this wild romanticism. His evidence in fact consists of unsupported
claims about the elitist psychology of individual anarchists and a few, out-of-context
quotations. Similarly, the only support Horowitz can give for his characterisation
(quoted above) comes from Denis Diderot, who, in Horowitz’s own words,
‘advocated a parliamentary monarchism in which representation would be elected by
the propertied classes’10, and was therefore clearly not an anarchist. In the face of
evidence this weak, it is tempting to dismiss the whole line of attack as a selfsustaining polemic.
However, there are two forms of this criticism which require a more detailed
response. I call them accusations of ‘primitivism’, for convenience and because each
can be related to one of the various meanings of ‘primitive’. This article will display,
3
analyse and refute two important forms of the assertion that anarchists are
primitivists.
‘Primitive’ is a complex term. It can mean unsophisticated, savage, stupid or
childish; pure; original or primary; low or simple; an early stage of evolution or
progress; a relic or survival in a world that has moved on. It can refer to people or
societies without our technology or without institutions like our states. ‘Primitive’
stands in some complex relation to a cluster of terms including ‘savage’, ‘native’,
‘aboriginal’, ‘undeveloped’, ‘unevolved’ and ‘prehistoric’, and also to opposing terms
like ‘civilised’, ‘developed’, ‘complex’, ‘sophisticated’ and ‘modern’. We should note
the term’s ideological weight: calling societies or people ‘primitive’ has often been
involved in, and even stood in for, justifications of marginalisation, oppression and
extermination. It can also be used in a less extreme but still polemical way, to indicate
a comfortable value judgement: ‘we are civilised, they are primitive.’
The two meanings of the term which relate to the criticisms of anarchism
under discussion here are primitive as pure, and primitive as original or primary. The
criticisms which involve these meanings are, respectively: the claim that anarchism
depends on an unrealistic notion of uncorrupted human nature (‘human nature
primitivism’); and the claim that anarchists are nostalgic for a mythical golden age
(‘golden age primitivism’). I define and respond to each in turn.
No comments:
Post a Comment