Mutual Aid:A Factor of EvolutionPeter Kropotkin[1902]
ALSO SEE
http://www.faculty.umb.edu/lawrence_blum/courses/306_12/readings/kropotkin_mutual.pdf
CONCLUSION
If we take now the teachings which can be borrowed from the
analysis of modern society, in connection with the body of evidence
relative to the importance of mutual aid in the evolution of the
animal world and of mankind, we may sum up our inquiry as follows.
In the animal world we have seen that the vast majority of
species live in societies, and that they find in association the
best arms for the struggle for life: understood, of course, in its
wide Darwinian sense — not as a struggle for the sheer means of
existence, but as a struggle against all natural conditions
unfavourable to the species. The animal species, in which individual
struggle has been reduced to its narrowest limits, and the practice
of mutual aid has attained the greatest development, are invariably
the most numerous, the most prosperous, and the most open to further
progress. The mutual protection which is obtained in this case, the
possibility of attaining old age and of accumulating experience, the
higher intellectual development, and the further growth of sociable
habits, secure the maintenance of the species, its extension, and
its further progressive evolution. The unsociable species, on the
contrary, are doomed to decay.
Going next over to man, we found him living in clans and tribes
at the very dawn of the stone age; we saw a wide series of social
institutions developed already in the lower savage stage, in the
clan and the tribe; and we found that the earliest tribal customs
and habits gave to mankind the embryo of all the institutions which
made later on the leading aspects of further progress. Out of the
savage tribe grew up the barbarian village community; and a new,
still wider, circle of social customs, habits, and institutions,
numbers of which are still alive among ourselves, was developed
under the principles of common possession of a given territory and
common defence of it, under the jurisdiction of the village
folkmote, and in the federation of villages belonging, or supposed
to belong, to one stem. And when new requirements induced men to
make a new start, they made it in the city, which represented a
double network of territorial units (village communities), connected
with guilds these latter arising out of the common prosecution of a
given art or craft, or for mutual support and defence.
And finally, in the last two chapters facts were produced to show
that although the growth of the State on the pattern of Imperial
Rome had put a violent end to all medieval institutions for mutual
support, this new aspect of civilization could not last. The State,
based upon loose aggregations of individuals and undertaking to be
their only bond of union, did not answer its purpose. The mutual-aid
tendency finally broke down its iron rules; it reappeared and
reasserted itself in an infinity of associations which now tend to
embrace all aspects of life and to take possession of all that is
required by man for life and for reproducing the waste occasioned by
life.
It will probably be remarked that mutual aid, even though it may
represent one of the factors of evolution, covers nevertheless one
aspect only of human relations; that by the side of this current,
powerful though it may be, there is, and always has been, the other
current — the self-assertion of the individual, not only in its
efforts to attain personal or caste superiority, economical,
political, and spiritual, but also in its much more important
although less evident function of breaking through the bonds, always
prone to become crystallized, which the tribe, the village
community, the city, and the State impose upon the individual. In
other words, there is the self-assertion of the individual taken as
a progressive element.
It is evident that no review of evolution can be complete, unless
these two dominant currents are analyzed. However, the
self-assertion of the individual or of groups of individuals, their
struggles for superiority, and the conflicts which resulted
therefrom, have already been analyzed, described, and glorified from
time immemorial. In fact, up to the present time, this current alone
has received attention from the epical poet, the annalist, the
historian, and the sociologist. History, such as it has hitherto
been written, is almost entirely a description of the ways and means
by which theocracy, military power, autocracy, and, later on, the
richer classes’ rule have been promoted, established, and
maintained. The struggles between these forces make, in fact, the
substance of history. We may thus take the knowledge of the
individual factor in human history as granted — even though there
is full room for a new study of the subject on the lines just
alluded to; while, on the other side, the mutual-aid factor has been
hitherto totally lost sight of; it was simply denied, or even
scoffed at, by the writers of the present and past generation. It
was therefore necessary to show, first of all, the immense part
which this factor plays in the evolution of both the animal world
and human societies. Only after this has been fully recognized will
it be possible to proceed to a comparison between the two factors.
To make even a rough estimate of their relative importance by any
method more or less statistical, is evidently impossible. One single
war — we all know — may be productive of more evil, immediate and
subsequent, than hundreds of years of the unchecked action of the
mutual-aid principle may be productive of good. But when we see that
in the animal world, progressive development and mutual aid go hand
in hand, while the inner struggle within the species is concomitant
with retrogressive development; when we notice that with man, even
success in struggle and war is proportionate to the development of
mutual aid in each of the two conflicting nations, cities, parties,
or tribes, and that in the process of evolution war itself (so far
as it can go this way) has been made subservient to the ends of
progress in mutual aid within the nation, the city or the clan — we
already obtain a perception of the dominating influence of the
mutual-aid factor as an element of progress. But we see also that
the practice of mutual aid and its successive developments have
created the very conditions of society life in which man was enabled
to develop his arts, knowledge, and intelligence; and that the
periods when institutions based on the mutual-aid tendency took
their greatest development were also the periods of the greatest
progress in arts, industry, and science. In fact, the study of the
inner life of the medieval city and of the ancient Greek cities
reveals the fact that the combination of mutual aid, as it was
practised within the guild and the Greek clan, with a large
initiative which was left to the individual and the group by means
of the federative principle, gave to mankind the two greatest
periods of its history — the ancient Greek city and the medieval
city periods; while the ruin of the above institutions during the
State periods of history, which followed, corresponded in both cases
to a rapid decay.
As to the sudden industrial progress which has been achieved
during our own century, and which is usually ascribed to the triumph
of individualism and competition, it certainly has a much deeper
origin than that. Once the great discoveries of the fifteenth
century were made, especially that of the pressure of the
atmosphere, supported by a series of advances in natural philosophy
— and they were made under the medieval city organization, — once
these discoveries were made, the invention of the steam-motor, and
all the revolution which the conquest of a new power implied, had
necessarily to follow. If the medieval cities had lived to bring
their discoveries to that point, the ethical consequences of the
revolution effected by steam might have been different; but the same
revolution in technics and science would have inevitably taken
place. It remains, indeed, an open question whether the general
decay of industries which followed the ruin of the free cities, and
was especially noticeable in the first part of the eighteenth
century, did not considerably retard the appearance of the
steam-engine as well as the consequent revolution in arts. When we
consider the astounding rapidity of industrial progress from the
twelfth to the fifteenth centuries — in weaving, working of metals,
architecture and navigation, and ponder over the scientific
discoveries which that industrial progress led to at the end of the
fifteenth century — we must ask ourselves whether mankind was not
delayed in its taking full advantage of these conquests when a
general depression of arts and industries took place in Europe after
the decay of medieval civilization. Surely it was not the
disappearance of the artist-artisan, nor the ruin of large cities
and the extinction of intercourse between them, which could favour
the industrial revolution; and we know indeed that James Watt spent
twenty or more years of his life in order to render his invention
serviceable, because he could not find in the last century what he
would have readily found in medieval Florence or Br gge, that is,
the artisans capable of realizing his devices in metal, and of
giving them the artistic finish and precision which the steam-engine
requires.
To attribute, therefore, the industrial progress of our century to
the war of each against all which it has proclaimed, is to reason
like the man who, knowing not the causes of rain, attributes it to
the victim he has immolated before his clay idol. For industrial
progress, as for each other conquest over nature, mutual aid and
close intercourse certainly are, as they have been, much more
advantageous than mutual struggle.
However, it is especially in the domain of ethics that. the
dominating importance of the mutual-aid principle appears in full.
That mutual aid is the real foundation of our ethical conceptions
seems evident enough. But whatever the opinions as to the first
origin of the mutual-aid feeling or instinct may be whether a
biological or a supernatural cause is ascribed to it — we must
trace its existence as far back as to the lowest stages of the
animal world; and from these stages we can follow its uninterrupted
evolution, in opposition to a number of contrary agencies, through
all degrees of human development, up to the present times. Even the
new religions which were born from time to time — always at epochs
when the mutual-aid principle was falling into decay in the
theocracies and despotic States of the East, or at the decline of
the Roman Empire — even the new religions have only reaffirmed that
same principle. They found their first supporters among the humble,
in the lowest, downtrodden layers of society, where the mutual-aid
principle is the necessary foundation of every-day life; and the new
forms of union which were introduced in the earliest Buddhist and
Christian communities, in the Moravian brotherhoods and so on, took
the character of a return to the best aspects of mutual aid i n
early tribal life.
Each time, however, that an attempt to return to this old
principle was made, its fundamental idea itself was widened. From
the clan it was extended to the stem, to the federation of stems, to
the nation, and finally — in ideal, at least — to the whole of
mankind. It was also refined at the same time. In primitive
Buddhism, in primitive Christianity, in the writings of some of the
Mussulman teachers, in the early movements of the Reform, and
especially in the ethical and philosophical movements of the last
century and of our own times, the total abandonment of the idea of
revenge, or of “due reward” — of good for good and evil
for evil — is affirmed more and more vigorously. The higher
conception of “no revenge for wrongs,” and of freely
giving more than one expects to receive from his neighbours, is
proclaimed as being the real principle of morality — a principle
superior to mere equivalence, equity, or justice, and more conducive
to happiness. And man is appealed to to be guided in his acts, not
merely by love, which is always personal, or at the best tribal, but
by the perception of his oneness with each human being. In the
practice of mutual aid, which we can retrace to the earliest
beginnings of evolution, we thus find the positive and undoubted
origin of our ethical conceptions; and we can affirm that in the
ethical progress of man, mutual support not mutual struggle — has
had the leading part. In its wide extension, even at the present
time, we also see the best guarantee of a still loftier evolution of
our race.
No comments:
Post a Comment