Friday, April 28, 2023

ELECTION MAY 29
Danielle Smith flips flops & takes credit for federal child-care program

April 21, 2023

There is something disorienting about Danielle Smith’s willingness – for the moment, anyway – to change her tune on opinions that she has advocated passionately throughout her career.
Alberta Premier Danielle Smith takes credit for Ottawa’s $10-a-day child care program in a campaign video.
 Credit: United Conservative Party


Alberta Premier Danielle Smith took to social media on Tuesday to take credit for the federal Liberal Government’s $10-a-day daycare plan, which Alta. only reluctantly signed onto and to which the province contributes nothing.

There is something disorienting about Smith’s willingness – for the moment, anyway – to change her tune on opinions that she has advocated passionately throughout her career, indeed, her entire adult life.

“We’re committed to ensuring all Albertans have the supports they need to succeed, including reliable, accessible, and affordable child care, so nobody has to choose between a family and a career,” Smith burbled cheerfully in a video distributed by the United Conservative Party (UCP) on social media.

The video has everything a good conservative needs for such a message: A new mom, a newborn, and a Neudorf, the latter being one of Smith’s two deputy premiers, Nathan, who is also the UCP MLA for Lethbridge East. (OK, that kid’s not exactly a newborn, but who could resist the sheer poetry of that image?)

“I’m committing that a re-elected United Conservative Government will ensure all Albertans have access to $10 a day daycare by 2026,” Smith vowed. “We’re proud of the agreement we’ve negotiated with the federal government, because it’s an amazing Alberta plan that works for Alberta families …”

In fairness, Smith tried hard to pretend that the deal Alta. signed onto with Ottawa was different from all those other provinces’ child-care deals because it gave a little more scope for private daycare operators.

Still, ’twas only the day before Christmas 2021 when all through the land Smith was carolling quite a different message, one much more in accord with the worldview she has long espoused.

Conservatism, she complained then, “is becoming indistinguishable from liberalism.

“All parties massively overspend, rack up debt, restrict businesses and deliver social programs exactly the same way,” she wrote in a Christmas Eve op-ed gleefully published by the Calgary Herald.

“A case in point is the new deal announced for child care. It was framed as returning $3.8 billion in federal tax revenue to Alberta. In practice, it’s given total control to Ottawa over how we deliver child care.” (Where’s the Sovereignty Act when you need it, she might have added, but didn’t, presumably because Rob Anderson, now her chief party ideologue and office manager, hadn’t thought it up yet.)

“If you put money in the hands of parents as consumers, they would decide which operators should get their business,” she argued. “Businesses could choose their own fee structure depending on their size, space, location, operating costs, staffing and salary. If an operator prices their services too high, having more options would give parents more ability to shop around.”

Yeah, right, as we say in our language, in which, grammatically speaking, a double positive isn’t supposed to imply a negative.

She moaned: “How could we sign a deal like this?”

She concluded: “It’s not too late to change course and tell Ottawa we are going to deliver child care the Alberta way.”

The Alberta way … And if she ever got to run Alberta, she didn’t say but obviously thought, she’d fix that up right smartly.

Public pressure being what it is, however, once she had the job she had to put that principle aside – at least until after the election scheduled for May 29, and until a suitable excuse can be found to deep-six it as unaffordable.

Like, say, if Smith’s man Pierre Poilievre ever gets the chance to eliminate the federal program.

“When you say about cutting supplementary spending,” the federal Conservative leader was asked a week before Smith’s op-ed appeared in the Herald, “in your view does that include the newly signed child care agreements with most of the provinces?”

Poilievre responded: “We have said we do not believe in a $100-billion slush fund to increase the cost of living on Canadians. We believe in putting money back in the pockets of the people who actually earned the money, and we believe in, uh, our proposal is to cancel tax increases, and cancel any new deficit spending.”

In other words, yes, it does.
 Foreign Affairs acknowledges Israel has destroyed the ‘two-state solution’

New article suggests unconditional backing of Israel may be losing support


Owen Schalk / April 19, 2023 
https://canadiandimension.com/

An elder waves the Palestinian flag near the boundary with Israel, east of Gaza City. Photo from Flickr.

Foreign Affairs is the magazine of the US foreign policy elite. Published by the Council on Foreign Relations, a meeting place for the political and business aristocracy to discuss issues relevant to US global power, the first issue included contributions from former Secretary of War and Secretary of State Elihu Root, former Harvard President Charles W. Eliot, and John Foster Dulles, then a “financial expert,” later a supporter of the Nazi government, and later still Eisenhower’s staunchly anti-communist secretary of state.

In 1947, Foreign Affairs publish George Kennan’s “Sources of Soviet Conduct” (also known as the “X” article), in which he claimed the Kremlin was committed to controlling “every nook and cranny… in the basin of world power,” and that Washington needed to “contain” Soviet influence by serving as a “counterforce” that could “increase enormously the strains under which Soviet policy must operate.”

The containment strategy was a defining feature of the US in the Cold War. It became official state policy when Truman’s National Security Council issued NSC-4A, which instructed the CIA to undertake “covert psychological activities” in support of anti-communism around the globe. Later, NSC-10/2 authorized the US state to undertake international efforts in “propaganda, economic warfare,” “sabotage,” and “subversion against hostile states including assistance to underground resistance movements.” Many consider Kennan’s article in Foreign Affairs the first articulation of this aggressive containment policy.

In addition to first publishing Kennan’s theory of containment, Foreign Affairs also published Harvard professor Samuel Huntington’s “Clash of Civilizations” article in 1993. Written in the triumphal hysteria of the Soviet Union’s collapse, Huntington claimed that with the overthrow of Soviet-style socialism, the age of ideology had ended; now, civilizations (or civilizational identities) were driving global conflicts. As such, major geopolitical disagreements of the day were primarily cultural rather than economic. This theory became the neoconservative explanation for terrorist attacks by Islamist groups and was adopted as the Bush administration’s framing of the War on Terror.

Throughout its history, Foreign Affairs has served as a forum for the mandarins of US imperialism to air such theories and debate ways to maintain or expand Western (and primarily US) dominance of the globe. As such, it is significant that the magazine recently published an article titled “Israel’s One-State Reality” that not only acknowledges the death of the two-state solution. The article goes further, correctly noting that the Israeli government’s drive to enshrine “Jewish supremacy over all Palestinians who remain there” is the reason that the two-state solution is no longer viable—and that Israel’s one-state apartheid system may end up damaging US influence in the long run.



In February 2022, Amnesty International recognized the reality that has been known to Palestinians since 1948: Israel is an apartheid state that “imposes a system of oppression and domination against Palestinians across all areas under its control.” B’Tselem, a human rights NGO based in Jerusalem, has also acknowledged that Israel “employs a regime of Jewish supremacy between the Jordan River and the Mediterranean Sea.”

While Israel has always been an apartheid state, the actions of the current coalition government—which many Israelis themselves have described as fascist—aim to cement the regime of Jewish supremacy even further. Even in the US and Canada, two of Israel’s most unwavering allies, it has been impossible to hide the fascist politics of powerful people in the coalition government. Itamar Ben-Gvir, current Minister of National Security, used to hang a portrait of mass murderer and terrorist Baruch Goldstein in his living room. Bezalel Smotrich, current Minister of Finance and administrator of the occupied West Bank, has described himself as a “homophobe, racist [and] fascist” and denied the existence of the Palestinian people.

At the same time, pogroms in towns like Huwara have effectively been endorsed by the state, even though Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahu publicly criticized settler extremists for “taking the law into their own hands.” Smotrich, meanwhile, celebrated the Huwara pogrom and called for the town to be “wiped out” by the Israeli army.

Recently, government attempts to strip power from the judiciary were met with unprecedented protests across Israel. While the reforms have been delayed, Netanyahu has given concessions to the extreme right in order to stay in power, such as allowing Ben-Gvir to create a “national guard” under his control, which critics have labelled a private militia.

By allying with the likes of Ben-Gvir and Smotrich, Netanyahu has taken the country so far to the right that he appears to be causing tensions with Israel’s most powerful backers in the West. The recent article in Foreign Affairs shows how this tension is influencing the thinking of an element of the US foreign policy elite.

Co-authored by four professors from George Washington University and the University of Maryland, two of whom are senior fellows at the Carnegie Endowment for International Peace and the Brookings Institution, the article begins:
Prime Minister Benjamin Netanyahu’s return to power in Israel with a narrow, extreme right-wing coalition has shattered even the illusion of a two-state solution… it is no longer possible to avoid confronting a one-state reality. Israel’s radical new government did not create this reality but rather made it impossible to deny. The temporary status of “occupation” of the Palestinian territories is now a permanent condition in which one state ruled by one group of people rules over another group of people.


The authors acknowledge that “Palestinians are permanently treated as a lower caste” in all areas under Israeli rule. They assert:
Policymakers and analysts who ignore this one-state reality will be condemned to failure and irrelevance, doing little beyond providing a smokescreen for the entrenchment of the status quo… Some implications of this one-state reality are clear. The world will not stop caring about Palestinian rights, no matter how fervently many supporters of Israel (and Arab rulers) wish they would. Violence, dispossession, and human rights abuses have escalated over the last year, and the risk of large-scale violent confrontation grows with every day that Palestinians are locked in this ever-expanding system of legalized oppression and Israeli encroachment.


The authors criticize Joe Biden for being totally committed to the status quo, doing nothing beyond “crisis management and mouthing displeasure.” As this is a Foreign Affairs article, their criticism is rooted in concern for US global standing, and the implications of Israel’s extreme-right turn on American interests in the region. In one passage, they write that the Netanyahu-led coalition government will likely incite “profound instability” in West Asia, “and a challenge to [the US government’s] broader global agenda.”

The article also recognizes that apartheid, defined by the International Criminal Court as “a legalized scheme of racial segregation and discrimination [that is] deemed a crime against humanity,” has moved to the mainstream of international discussions about Israel. The Israeli government’s rightward drift and its destruction of the two-state possibility have made its apartheid system harder to ignore.

The now meaningless “peace process” served as an excuse for Western observers to overlook Israel’s oppression of Palestinians and its treatment of areas under its occupation—if a Palestinian state was possible, the argument went, then Israel’s domination would eventually recede and the Palestinians would be allowed to organize themselves according to their own wishes. That didn’t happen, and it won’t.

“All these diversions are gone,” the authors write. “The one-state reality has long been embedded in Israeli law, politics, and society… Daily acts of violence and sporadic bouts of popular upheaval—perhaps even a full third Intifada—seem inevitable.”

Under President Donald Trump, Washington made efforts to separate Israel’s normalization with Arab countries from Palestinian rights, a campaign that culminated in the Abraham Accords. However, Palestine remains an important issue to people across the region. The authors note that if the Israeli government expels Palestinians from the West Bank or Jerusalem, or takes actions that provoke the collapse of the Palestinian Authority, regional protests would be widespread and difficult for the US and its client states to manage, especially given the role that Hamas and Iran would play in such a conflagration.

As the possibility of a greater conflict rises, Washington continues to cling to outdated rhetoric around Israel-Palestine—a persistence that is wholly out-of-step with the US public, whose religious right-wing is slowly becoming the only demographic that supports unconditional support for Israeli policies.

The authors suggest that Washington should condition its military and economic aid to Israel “on clear and specific measures to terminate Israel’s military rule over the Palestinians.” If Israel refuses, they write, the US should reduce aid and level sanctions against the state. At the same time, they argue that Washington needs to stop “shielding Israel in international organizations” and “vetoing UN Security Council resolutions that aim to hold Israel accountable.”

“By finally confronting the one-state reality and taking a principled stand,” they conclude, “the United States would stop being part of the problem and start being part of the solution.”

Despite the article’s flaws—an odd reference to the dangers of a “populist world,” a clearly fanciful view of “liberal democracies” and the “liberal international order,” and unwarranted praise for Biden’s supposedly “full-throated defense of international laws and norms” following Russia’s invasion of Ukraine—this is an important piece of writing that calls for a wide-ranging reappraisal of US-Israel relations. The fact that it appears in Foreign Affairs makes it even more fascinating, and suggests that amongst a certain segment of the America’s foreign policy elite, the unconditional backing of Israel may be losing support.

Owen Schalk is a writer from Manitoba. His book on Canada’s role in the war in Afghanistan will be released by Lorimer in September. You can preorder it here. To see more of his work, visit www.owenschalk.com.
Canada Post issues mass suspension for workers exercising their right to complain

Edmonton workers asked for five minutes to voice concerns. Then they were hit with five-day suspensions and final warnings


Brett McKay / April 3, 2023 / 

CUPW members strike at a Canada Post facility in Edmonton. Photo courtesy Edmonton and District Labour Council.

For months workers at a Canada Post mail processing plant in Edmonton had been complaining of conditions that they felt jeopardized their safety and wellbeing in the workplace.

Recent changes required employees to lift heavier objects more frequently than in the past. Routine safety talks and site walkthroughs were not being performed. The long-established practice of trading duties with other workers was revoked, and problems with staffing and scheduling were putting staff at greater risk of injury, the employees said.

When management failed to address these issues, workers put their concerns in writing. Staff circulated a petition that was signed by the majority of employees in their section and scheduled a meeting with management on February 16 to present the letter and have their grievances heard.

In a surprising escalation resulting from management’s refusal to hear these complaints at that meeting, police were called, charges threatened, and over 40 postal workers were suspended without pay.

“Canada Post issued a five-day suspension for every single worker that was involved, served consecutively the following week,” said Devon Rundvall, president of the Canadian Union of Postal Workers Local 730, which represents workers at the Edmonton facility. “The reality is Canada Post refused a five-minute conversation and instead issued six and a half months of suspensions.”

“It’s very disheartening and frustrating, because how can we as workers bring up our concerns about our working environment related to health and safety if we can’t have management speak with us when we request them to?” said Mark, one of the roughly 40 workers who received a five-day suspension.

Mark’s real name is being withheld because they fear their job would be threatened if they were identified.

Leading up to the incident on February 16, Rundvall said that workers had already been filing grievances and “doing everything that we’re told that we’re supposed to do to get results, to get justice, to get change. And time and time again, for months on end, Canada Post just refused to address any of these issues.”

It was the recognition of how slow and ineffectual the bureaucratic process can be that prompted workers to take more direct action to improve conditions. Problems in the workplace had come to a point where “people were no longer able to just silently suffer and deal with it,” Mark said. “I think a health and safety issue should be investigated immediately. Whether or not the corporation thinks it’s valid, how could they know if they haven’t heard the concern?”

When the 40 workers and their union president gathered on the shop floor, management again tried to refuse the meeting.

“[The manager] refused to talk to us, he would not listen to anything we said. He just kept trying to send us to work, telling us that the meeting wasn’t going to happen that what we were doing was grandstanding,” Mark said.

The workers stood their ground and waited. After two hours a labour relations representative arrived and listened to the groups’ concerns. “Then she told us that what we were doing was considered an illegal work stoppage,” Mark said.

“We didn’t see it that way. Because at any moment, management could have given that five minutes and we would have went back to work. So, we felt like this time delay in hard work was all up to management. They had the control.”

Around the same time, the Canada Post head of security pulled Rundvall aside to tell him that the police had arrived, and he would be arrested and charged with either disturbing the peace or delay of mail under the Canada Post Act.

“By the time I made it to the front, there were three Edmonton Police officers waiting for me, cuffs in hand, waiting for the order to arrest me to come across the radio. It didn’t come. I guess their boss told him let them go. And that was the end of it,” Rundvall said.

Management has since said that the reason the police were called was “because the shift manager felt like he was in danger,” Rundvall told Canadian Dimension. “Which is quite laughable.”

While Rundvall was never charged, all of the workers involved have now been served with suspensions and final warnings. It’s a move that CUPW says is an attack on all of its members, silencing workers from reporting job hazards and contract violations.

“The expectations of employees are detailed in our collective agreements and our internal code of conduct. Beyond that, we don’t comment publicly on personnel matters,” a media relations representative from Canada Post said in an e-mailed statement.

“We felt like they were violating our rights,” Mark said, noting CUPW workers have the right to complain under their collective agreement.

“We all have the same issues. we all have the same concerns. And when those concerns aren’t being addressed, and when these problems aren’t being rectified, at some point you’re going to exercise what options you have.”

A fundraiser has been set up to cover the lost wages of the suspended workers and has so far raised nearly $2,500.

Brett McKay is a writer and journalist based in Edmonton, AB. You can contact him here.
The state and the future of socialism
When capital is in crisis, there are always two options—to give in or to move in

Michael A. Lebowitz / April 25, 2023
https://canadiandimension.com/

Wojciech Fangor, “Forging the Scythes” (1954). 
Image courtesy the Museum of Warsaw.

REALLY LONG READ

The following essay by Marxist economist Michael A. Lebowitz was first published in the 2013 edition of Socialist Register. Lebowitz, who passed away on April 19, 2023 at the age of 85, was a giant of the socialist left. Over the years, Canadian Dimension published several of his essays. He taught at Simon Fraser University for decades and was the author of numerous books including Beyond Capital: Marx’s Political Economy of the Working Class and Build It Now: Socialism for the 21st Century. He was Director, Program in Transformative Practice and Human Development, Centro Internacional Miranda, in Caracas, Venezuela, from 2006-11.

We are in the midst of a class war. That’s not unusual. There is always class war in capitalism—although sometimes it is hidden and sometimes there is the interlude of an apparent Carthaginian Peace. But the class war has intensified now because of the crisis in capitalism—a crisis rooted in the over-accumulation of capital. And, in this crisis, capital has intensified the class war against the working class. Austerity, cutbacks, the need to sacrifice—these are the demands of capital as it calls upon workers to bear the burden of capital’s own failures. This is a war conducted by capitalist states against workers to compel them to give up their achievements from past struggles. And, in some places (but, unfortunately, not all), we see that the working class is saying, ‘no.’ In some cases, we see that workers are fighting to defend their past successes within capitalism and that they are fighting against the racism and xenophobia which are the default position when workers are under attack but are not in struggle against capital. Such struggles, as Marx knew, are ‘indispensable’—they are the only means of preventing workers ‘from becoming apathetic, thoughtless, more or less well-fed instruments of production.’ But, who will win this class war?

In his recent book, The Communist Hypothesis, Alain Badiou describes the past defeats of May 1968, the Chinese Cultural Revolution and the Paris Commune as well as those of factory occupations and other such struggles as defeats ‘covered with glory.’ Because they remain in our memory as inspirations, they must be contrasted, he insists, to the ‘defeat without glory’ that social democracy brings. This is certainly true. However, we need to acknowledge that the current struggles against capital’s attempt to make the working class rescue it from yet another of its crises may yet be added to the list of glorious defeats. Of course, it is necessary to try to stop the cutbacks and to communicate to capital how high its costs will be for attempting to shift the burden of its own failures to workers. And, of course, we must celebrate those struggles taking place wherever the working class has not been anesthetized as a result of previous defeats without glory, leaving only what Marx once described as ‘a heart-broken, a weak-minded, a worn-out, unresisting mass.’

But it is not enough to say ‘no.’ There are those who think that an accumulation of loudly screamed no’s can be sufficient—let alone the ‘silent farts’ celebrated by John Holloway. These poets of negation demonstrate thereby that they don’t understand why and how capital reproduces itself. Why is it that after so many defeats so many still cannot see what Marx grasped in the nineteenth century – that capital has the tendency to produce a working class which views the existence of capital as necessary? ‘The advance of capitalist production,’ he stressed, ‘develops a working class which by education, tradition and habit looks upon the requirements of this mode of production as self-evident natural laws.’

Marx understood that capitalism tends to produce the workers it needs, workers who look upon capitalism as common sense. Given the mystification of capital (arising from the sale of labour-power) which makes productivity, profits and progress appear as the result of the capitalist’s contribution, it followed that ‘the organization of the capitalist process of production, once it is fully developed, breaks down all resistance.’

And, Marx added that capital’s generation of a reserve army of the unemployed ‘sets the seal on the domination of the capitalist over the worker’ and that the capitalist can rely upon the worker’s ‘dependence on capital, which springs from the conditions of production themselves, and is guaranteed in perpetuity by them.’ Obviously, for Marx, capital’s walls will never be brought down by loud screams or silent farts.

Even with a certain resistance marked by struggles over wages, working conditions and the defence of past gains, as long as workers look upon the requirements of capital as ‘self-evident natural laws,’ those struggles occur within the bounds of the capitalist relation. In the end, workers’ subordination to the logic of capital means that faced with capitalism’s crises they sooner or later act to ensure the conditions for the expanded reproduction of capital. Nowhere is this clearer than in the defeats without glory of social democracy.

And, defeat when capitalism is in crisis means that capital can emerge from the crisis by restructuring itself—as it did internationally with the Bretton Woods package after the crises of the 1930s and the 1970s. As is often noted, there is a big difference between a crisis in capitalism and a crisis of capitalism. The latter requires conscious actors prepared to put an end to capitalism, prepared to challenge and defeat the logic of capital. But this requires a vision which can appear to workers as an alternative common sense, as their common sense.

Like the ‘worst architect,’ we must build our goal in our minds before we can construct it in reality; only this conscious focus can ensure the ‘purposeful will’ required to complete the defeat of the logic of capital. To struggle against a situation in which workers ‘by education, tradition and habit’ look upon capital’s needs ‘as self-evident natural laws,’ we must struggle for an alternative common sense. But what is the vision of a new society whose requirements workers may look upon as ‘self-evident natural laws’? Clearly, it won’t be found in the results of twentieth century attempts to build socialism, which, to use Marx’s phrase, ended ‘in a miserable fit of the blues.’
The ‘key link’ for twenty-first century socialism

‘We have to reinvent socialism.’ With this statement, Hugo Chavez, President of Venezuela, electrified activists in his closing speech at the January 2005 World Social Forum in Porto Alegre, Brazil. ‘It can’t be the kind of socialism that we saw in the Soviet Union,’ he stressed, ‘but it will emerge as we develop new systems that are built on cooperation, not competition.’ If we are ever going to end the poverty of the majority of the world, capitalism must be transcended, Chavez argued. ‘But we cannot resort to state capitalism, which would be the same perversion of the Soviet Union. We must reclaim socialism as a thesis, a project and a path, but a new type of socialism, a humanist one, which puts humans and not machines or the state ahead of everything.’

There, at its core, is the vision of socialism for the twenty-first century. Rather than expansion of the means of production or direction by the state, human beings must be at the centre of the new socialist society. This marks a return to Marx’s vision—to the contrast he drew in Capital between a society subordinate to the logic of capital (where ‘the worker exists to satisfy the need of the existing values for valorization’) and the logic of a new society, that ‘inverse situation, in which objective wealth is there to satisfy the worker’s own need for development.’ This concept of the worker’s need for development is the culmination of Marx’s consistent stress upon the centrality of the development of human capacity—the ‘development of the rich individuality,’ as the real wealth and explicit goal of the new society. Here was the ‘inverse situation’ which would allow for ‘the all-round development of the individual,’ the ‘complete working out of the human content,’ the ‘development of all human powers as such the end in itself,’ a society of associated producers in which ‘the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all.’

But this is only one side of Marx’s perspective. A focus upon the full development of human potential was characteristic of much socialist thought in the nineteenth century. What Marx added to this emphasis upon human development was his understanding of how that development of human capacities occurs. In his Theses on Feuerbach, he was quite clear that it is not by giving people gifts, not by changing circumstances for them. Rather, we change only through real practice, by changing circumstances ourselves. Marx’s concept of ‘revolutionary practice,’ that concept of ‘the coincidence of the changing of circumstances and of human activity or self-change,’ is the red thread that runs throughout his work. Marx was most consistent on this point when talking about the struggles of workers against capital and how this revolutionary practice transforms ‘circumstances and men,’ expanding their capabilities and making them fit to create a new world.

But this process of changing ourselves is not at all limited to the sphere of political and economic struggle. In the very act of producing, Marx indicated, ‘the producers change, too, in that they bring out new qualities in themselves, develop themselves in production, transform themselves, develop new powers and new ideas, new modes of intercourse, new needs and new language.’ And, certainly, the relations within which workers produce affect the nature of the workers produced. After all, that was Marx’s point about how capitalist productive relations ‘distort the worker into a fragment of a man’ and degrade him and ‘alienate from him the intellectual potentialities of the labour process.’ It is essential to recognize that every human activity has as its result a joint product—both the change in the object of labour and the change in the labourer herself. Unfortunately, that second product is often forgotten.

Marx’s combination of human development and practice constitutes the key link. Taken seriously, it has definite implications for relations within the workplace – rather than capitalism’s joint product (the fragmented, crippled human being whose enjoyment consists in possessing and consuming things), it implies a person who is able to develop all her potential through her activity. Taken seriously, that key link has definite implications for the nature of the state—rather than allowing us every few years to elect those who misrule us as our representatives to a state which stands over and above us, it implies what Marx called the ‘self-government of the producers,’ the ‘reabsorption of the state power by society as its own living forces.’ Taken seriously, that key link has definite implications for the nature of the party—rather than a body that sees itself as superior to social movements and whose members are meant to learn the merits of discipline in following the decisions made by infallible central committees, it implies a party which learns from popular initiative and unleashes the creative energy of masses through their own practice. Taken seriously, that key link has obvious implications for building socialism.

Consider the characteristic of socialist production implicit in this key link. What are the circumstances that have as their joint product ‘the totally developed individual, for whom the different social functions are different modes of activity he takes up in turn’? Given the ‘dialectical inversion’ peculiar to capitalist production that cripples the body and mind of the worker and alienates her from ‘the intellectual potentialities of the labour process,’ it is clear that to develop the capacities of people the producers must put an end to what Marx called, in his Critique of the Gotha Programme, ‘the enslaving subordination of the individual to the division of labour, and therewith also the antithesis between mental and physical labour.’

For the development of rich human beings, the worker must be able to call ‘his own muscles into play under the control of his own brain.’ Expanding the capabilities of people requires both mental and manual activity. Not only does the combination of education with productive labour make it possible to increase the efficiency of production; this is also, as Marx pointed out in Capital, ‘the only method of producing fully developed human beings.’ Here, then, is the way to ensure that ‘the productive forces have also increased with the all-around development of the individual, and all the springs of co-operative wealth flow more abundantly.’

The activity through which people develop their capacities, however, is not limited to the sphere of production as narrowly defined within capitalism. Every activity with the goal of providing inputs into the development of human beings needs be understood as an aspect of production. And the goals that guide production must be democratically established so that people can transform both their circumstances and themselves and thereby produce themselves as subjects in the new society. The implication is obvious—every aspect of production must be a site for the collective decision-making and variety of activity that develops human capacities and builds solidarity among the particular associated producers.

When workers act in workplaces and communities in conscious cooperation with others, they produce themselves as people conscious of their interdependence and of their own collective power. The joint product of their activity is the development of the capacities of the producers—precisely Marx’s point when he says that ‘when the worker cooperates in a planned way with others, he strips off the fetters of his individuality, and develops the capabilities of his species.’ Creating the conditions in workplaces and communities by which people can develop their capacities is an essential aspect of the concept of socialism for the twenty-first century. But it is only one element. How can the worker’s own need for development be realized if capital owns our social heritage—the products of the social brain and the social hand? And, how can we develop our own potential if we look upon other producers as enemies or as our markets—i.e., if individual material self-interest is our motivation?

Capitalism is an organic system, one which has the tendency to reproduce the conditions of its existence (including a working class which looks upon its requirements as ‘self-evident natural laws’). That is its strength. To counter that and to satisfy ‘the worker’s own need for development,’ the socialist alternative also must be an organic system, a particular combination of production, distribution and consumption, a system of reproduction. What Chavez named in January 2007 as ‘the elementary triangle of socialism’ (social property, social production and satisfaction of social needs) is a step forward toward a conception of such a system.

Consider the logic of this socialist combination, this conception of socialism for the twenty-first century:

1. Social ownership of the means of production is critical within this structure because it is the only way to ensure that our communal, social productivity is directed to the free development of all rather than used to satisfy the private goals of capitalists, groups of producers or state bureaucrats. But, this concerns more than our current activity. Social ownership of our social heritage, the results of past social labour, is an assertion that all living human beings have the right to the full development of their potential—to real wealth, the development of human capacity. It is the recognition that ‘the free development of each is the condition for the free development of all.’

2. Social production organized by workers builds new relations among producers—relations of cooperation and solidarity. It allows workers to end ‘the crippling of body and mind’ and the loss of ‘every atom of freedom, both in bodily and in intellectual activity’ that comes from the separation of head and hand. Organization of production in all spheres by workers, thus, is a condition for the full development of the producers, for the development of their capabilities—a condition for the production of rich human beings.

3. Satisfaction of communal needs and purposes as the goal of productive activity means that, instead of interacting as separate and indifferent individuals, we function as members of a community. Rather than looking upon our own capacity as our property and as a means of securing as much as possible in an exchange, we start from the recognition of our common humanity and, thus, of the importance of conditions in which everyone is able to develop her full potential. When our productive activity is oriented to the needs of others, it both builds solidarity among people and produces socialist human beings.

These three sides of the ‘socialist triangle’ mutually interact to form a structure in which ‘all the elements coexist simultaneously and support one another,’ as Marx put it. ‘This is the case with every organic whole.’ Yet, the very interdependence of the three sides suggests that realization of each element depends upon the existence of the other two. Without production for social needs, no real social property; without social property, no worker decision-making oriented toward society’s needs; without worker decision-making, no transformation of people and their needs.

The state’s place within ‘socialism as an organic system’

Is there a place for the state in socialism as an organic system? In the absence of a mechanism by which this particular combination of production, distribution and consumption can be realized, it remains purely a vision. Thus, implicit in the concept of socialism as an organic system is a set of institutions and practices through which all members of society can share the fruits of social labour and are able to satisfy their ‘own need for development.’ To produce and reproduce ‘rich human beings’ in a society based upon solidarity requires a conscious attempt to ensure that the necessary conditions for full human development infuse all levels of society.

Consider one possible scenario for a process of participatory diagnosis and planning. At the level of an individual neighbourhood, it is possible for neighbours to discuss directly the kind of community they want to live in and what they see as necessary for the development of their capacities and that of those around them. While this process identifies needs, the discussion also allows this community to explore its own ability to satisfy those needs itself; in other words, it identifies the capabilities of the community. Thus, at the level of the community, there is a direct attempt to coordinate the system of needs and the system of labours. In addition to being able to identify its needs and the extent to which those can be satisfied locally through the labour of community members, this process (which occurs under the guidance of elected neighbourhood councils) has a second product. By sharing and attempting to reconcile views of the most urgent needs of members of this community, there is a learning process—one in which protagonism builds and reinforces solidarity—i.e., the process of participatory diagnosis produces particular people, a particular joint product. At the core of this process, thus, is revolutionary practice—the simultaneous changing of circumstances and human activity or self-change.

Of course, the probability of a precise match between capabilities and needs within this community is negligible. The community is likely to have needs it cannot satisfy locally and capacities it does not need. In this situation, autarky supports neither the ability of people to secure the use-values they identify as important for their development nor the satisfaction in meaningful activity that can come from meeting the needs of others outside their immediate neighbourhood. Thus, to satisfy ‘the worker’s own need for development,’ the community needs to go beyond this barrier in order to coordinate with other communities in a larger body.

The commune represents a further step, bringing together the information transmitted by local neighbourhood councils about the needs and capabilities of their communities as well as drawing upon the knowledge of workers within units of production in this geographical area. Do workers have the capacity to satisfy the needs identified by the communities? By exploring this question in their workers councils, workers engage in conscious consideration of production options within their workplaces and focus upon the logic of producing for communal needs; however, to answer this question adequately requires more than responses from individual production units taken separately. By combining their knowledge and capabilities, workers in particular workplaces can achieve results which are greater than the sum of their individual parts taken separately. But, here again, more than a process of producing for communal needs and purposes occurs. Cooperation within and between units of production for this purpose generates solidarity among the combined workers and reinforces their understanding of the goals of production.

Throughout this process, community members and workers can interact through communal meetings and a communal parliament. And, the result of the process is that the commune councils have at their disposal data on (a) needs that can be satisfied from within the commune and (b) the needs which cannot be satisfied locally. Further, there is information on (c) the potential output of workplaces that can be provisionally utilized within the commune, and (d) the potential output of workplaces that is unutilized. Thus, there is both an indication of the level of needs that provisionally can be satisfied locally as well as identification of the excess demand and excess supply within each commune.

To stop here would reproduce the problem of remaining at the level of the individual neighbourhood. To create the conditions for the free development of all, it is necessary to go beyond geographical barriers. Thus, this process is extended to larger areas: the data from communes is transmitted upward to cities (communal cities), to the states or provinces and ultimately to the national level – to bodies composed of delegates from the communes, cities and the states, respectively. At the national level, then, it is possible to identify (a) provisionally satisfied needs, (b) unsatisfied needs, (c) provisionally assigned output and (d) provisionally unassigned output. It is fair to assume that there will not be a balance between needs and capacities at the first iteration.

Accordingly, the process of reconciling the system of needs and the system of labours is an essential requirement of the set of institutions and practices characteristic of socialism as an organic system. If there are excess needs, there are two logical resorts: (1) find a way to increase output (a question for workers councils to explore), and (2) recognize the necessity to reduce satisfaction of some needs. Thus, a critical discussion must occur here—what is to be unsatisfied? Exploration of this question requires a discussion of the relative requirements of different areas and the different types of needs to be given priority. It is only at this level that identification of national and regional inequality occurs as well as a discussion of priorities and choices for the society as a whole. This dialogue needs to take place not only at the national level but at every level down to the neighbourhood. Such a discussion is absolutely essential because, through such a process of participatory planning, people learn about the needs and capacities of others elsewhere in the society. There is no other way to build solidarity than to put faces upon other members of society. Thus, throughout this process, there are two products: development of the plan and the development of the people who participate in its construction.

The result of this scenario is a process of production for communal needs and communal purposes in which protagonism within the workplace and community ensures that this is social production organized by the producers. Obviously, too, the third side of the socialist triangle, social ownership, is present in that there is neither production for capital nor production for any particular group, i.e. a process of group ownership. In each workplace, workers are conscious that their productive activity is for society. In short, begin with communality, and the product of our activity is ‘a communal, general product from the outset.’

How, though, could the concept of socialism as an organic system be made real in the absence of institutions and practices such as these? This combination and articulation of councils and delegates at different levels of society is necessary to ensure the reproduction of a society in which the ‘free development of each is the condition for the free development of all.’ And, it is a state—a particular type of state, a state from below, a state of the commune-type. This state does not wither away—rather, it is an integral part of socialism as an organic system.

Of course, some people may not wish to call this set of institutions a state because these are society’s ‘own living forces’—i.e., not ‘an organ standing above society’ but ‘one completely subordinate to it.’ How would designation of this as a state be compatible with the view that, by definition, as Holloway puts it, ‘the state is the assassin of hope’? Like those who conceive of labour as inherently a burden (and thus can think of nothing better than to reduce it to zero), those who reject these institutions as a state demonstrate that they are trapped in the categories of old societies.

Old habits die slowly, though. And, taxonomy should not trump content. So, if some people prefer to call these articulated councils a non-state or the ‘Unstate,’ this should not present a problem—as long as they agree that socialism as an organic system requires these institutions and practices in order to be real.


Michael A. Lebowitz. Photo from Flickr.


Subordinating the old society: Contested reproduction


However, an organic system does not drop from the sky. In socialism as an organic system (to paraphrase Marx’s description of capitalism as an organic system), ‘every economic relation presupposes every other in its [socialist] economic form, and everything posited is thus also a presupposition, this is the case with every organic system.’ Yet, a new system never produces its own premises at the outset. Rather, when a new system emerges, it necessarily inherits premises from the old. Its premises and presuppositions are ‘historic’ ones, premises which are produced outside the system and which thus do not arise upon its own foundations.

In short, every new system as it emerges is inevitably defective: it is ‘in every respect, economically, morally and intellectually, still stamped with the birth marks of the old society.’ Accordingly, the development of an organic system is a process of becoming. ‘Its development to its totality,’ Marx indicated, ‘consists precisely in subordinating all elements of society to itself, or in creating out of it the organs which it still lacks. This is historically how it becomes a totality.’

In the 1920s, the Soviet economist Evgeny Preobrazhensky made this very point about how a new system develops. ‘Not a single economic formation,’ he argued, ‘can develop in a pure form, on the basis merely of the immanent laws which are inherent to the particular formation. This would be in contradiction to the very idea of development. The development of any economic form means its ousting of other economic forms, the subordination of these forms to the new form, and their gradual elimination.’ So, what is to be subordinated? If socialism is to develop into an organic system, social ownership of the means of production must supplant private ownership; worker management must replace despotism in the workplace; and productive activity based upon solidarity and community must subordinate individual self-interest. And, of course, the old state must be transcended, replaced by the new organs which foster the simultaneous changing of circumstances and self-change.

Obviously, this cannot happen overnight. It also, however, is something that cannot take place in stages. The idea of putting off some questions until a later stage is prepared is alien to a concept of an organic system. The continued presence of elements of capitalism does not simply mean that socialism is at yet incomplete because a few parts are missing. After all, what kinds of people are produced within the old relations? In fact, every moment that people act within old relations is a process of reproducing old ideas and attitudes. Working within a hierarchy, functioning without the ability to make decisions in the workplace and society, focusing upon self-interest rather than upon solidarity—these activities produce people on a daily basis; it is the reproduction of the conservatism of everyday life—indeed, the reproduction of elements of capitalism.

The concept of socialism for the twenty-first century as an organic system theoretically posits what the experience of the twentieth century has demonstrated – the need to build all sides of the socialist triangle. One war, three fronts. In the absence of a struggle to subordinate all the elements of the old society, the new society is inevitably infected by the old society. And, the matter is worse if we choose homeopathic medicine to cure the infection. In short, rather than build upon defects (such as the orientation toward material self-interest that Marx warned about in his Critique of the Gotha Programme), the point is to subordinate them.

Just as capitalism, though, required the development of a specifically capitalist mode of production to be an organic system, socialism also cannot subordinate all elements of society to itself until it develops a specifically socialist mode of production. Consider capitalism before it developed to the point where it produced its own premises in their capitalist form—i.e., when it was still in the process of becoming. That process of becoming necessarily involved the contracted reproduction of the existing relations—relations Marx described as ones in which the producer ‘as owner of his own conditions of labour, employs that labour to enrich himself instead of the capitalist.’ The separation of producers from those means of production and the compulsion to sell their labour-power marked the beginning of capitalist relations. Wherever possible, however, workers attempted to extract themselves and to become independent producers rather than to sell their ‘birth-right for a mess of pottage.’ This possibility was always present as wages increased with the accumulation of capital in the absence of the specifically capitalist mode of production. ‘Two diametrically opposed economic systems’ were present—and not only in the colonies where the problem of non-reproduction of wage-labourers was most marked.

The struggle over the subordination of the elements of production, thus, did not end with the original (or primitive) development of capitalist relations of production. Reproduction of those new relations was not secure until the development of the specifically capitalist mode of production that ensures reproduction of the premises of the system. ‘As soon as capitalist production stands on its own feet,’ Marx noted, ‘it not only maintains this separation [between workers and the means of production] but reproduces it on a constantly extending scale.’ Until capital developed upon its own foundations, however, differing relations and differing logics existed simultaneously.

So, what happens when differing relations coexist? Rather than peaceful coexistence, there is contested reproduction—with each system attempting to expand at the expense of the other. Considering the Soviet Union in the 1920s, Preobrazhensky argued that the state economy was in ‘an uninterrupted economic war with the tendencies of capitalist development, with the tendencies of capitalist restoration.’ This, he proposed, was a ‘struggle between two mutually hostile systems,’ a war between two regulating principles—one, the result of the spontaneous effects of commodity—capitalist relations (‘the law of value’); and the other, based upon the conscious decisions of the regulatory organs of the state (which he called ‘the law of primitive socialist accumulation’). And, Preobrazhensky argued that each of these regulating principles was ‘fighting for the type of regulation which is organically characteristic of the particular system of production-relations, taken in its pure form.’ However, the result of their interaction was that the Soviet economy was regulated by neither in its pure form. There was not a simple combination or addition of the productive relations and their associated regulating principles; rather, they interpenetrated—coexisting, limiting and (significantly) deforming each other.

Preobrazhensky’s insight, in short, was that in the process of becoming of a new system, two systems and two logics do not simply exist side-by-side. They interact. They interpenetrate. And, they deform each other. Rather than the combination permitting the best of both worlds, the effect can be the worst of the two worlds. Precisely because there is contested reproduction between differing sets of productive relations, the interaction of the systems can generate crises, inefficiencies and irrationality that wouldn’t be found in either system in its purity. Accordingly, as is well known, Preobrazhensky argued that rather than search for balance between the two, it was essential that what he called primitive socialist accumulation subordinate and replace the law of value.

But consider capitalism in its process of becoming. How, in the absence of the specifically capitalist mode of production, were capitalist relations of production reproduced? After all, the interaction between what Marx had called ‘two diametrically opposed economic systems’ was definitely producing problems that would not occur outside that combination. This was exactly what was occurring when the labour-intensive accumulation of capital produced a tendency for the non-reproduction of wage-labour as the result of rising wages. Marx was quite clear on what capital’s answer was—i.e., how capital ensured the reproduction of capitalist relations of production under these conditions. He detailed the measures undertaken with the emergence of capitalism—‘the bloody discipline,’ the ‘police methods,’ ‘the state compulsion to confine the struggle between capital and labour within limits convenient for capital.’ In direct contrast to the conditions for the reproduction of capitalist relations once the specifically capitalist mode of production has been developed, he argued that ‘the rising bourgeoisie needs the power of the state, and uses it to “regulate” wages.’

In short, until capital produced its own premises with the development of the specifically capitalist mode of production, it needed what I have called a ‘capitalist mode of regulation’—a mode of regulation which could ensure the compatibility of the behaviour of workers with the requirements of capital. In the absence of what Marx called ‘the sheer force of economic relations,’ that specific mode of regulation relied upon the coercive power of the state to prevent wages from rising and to compel workers (through ‘grotesquely terroristic laws’) ‘into accepting the discipline necessary for the system of wage-labour.’

The necessity of a socialist mode of regulation

Can the associated producers, in their turn, use such a state to support socialist productive relations before the development of socialism as an organic system? Consider the situation described in the Communist Manifesto where the ‘battle of democracy’ has been won (through a revolutionary rupture or a longer process) with the result that a government representing workers exists. At every step in the process of the becoming of socialism, the elements of capitalism and socialism (‘two diametrically opposed economic systems’) will interact and produce systemic incoherence and crisis. For example, when capitalist elements dominate, attempts to subordinate or make ‘despotic inroads’ upon them will tend to generate a capital strike and an economic crisis. If a government is prepared to break with the logic of capital, it will understand (as the Manifesto indicates) that it is ‘compelled to go always further’ and to make ‘further inroads upon the old social order’ and thus to ‘wrest, by degrees, all capital from the bourgeoisie, to centralize all instruments of production in the hands of the State.’ In contrast, the sorry history of social democracy has been that, sooner or later, it yields to the logic of capital and reinforces its rule.

A socialist mode of regulation must achieve consciously what a specifically socialist mode of production will tend to do spontaneously—ensure the reproduction of socialist relations of production. The building and reproduction of those relations (represented by the sides of the socialist triangle) ‘consists precisely in subordinating all elements of society to itself, or in creating out of it the organs which it still lacks.’ Thus, the socialist mode of regulation must subordinate consciously every element which supports the old society—both the institutions and the common sense that supports those old relations. Further, it must create new socialist elements which can become the premises and foundation for the new society.

The socialist mode of regulation, accordingly, must embrace the Battle of Ideas—the ideological struggle oriented toward human development. It must stress how the logic of capital is contrary to the development of our potential, and it must use every example of capital’s response to measures supportive of human development as yet another demonstration of the perversion of capitalism. Further, the acceptance of the logic of capital as ‘self-evident natural laws’ must be challenged by development of a coherent alternative which stresses the importance of democratic, participatory and protagonistic practice in workplaces and communities and emphasizes a new social rationality based upon cooperation and solidarity. Of course, an ideological struggle cannot succeed by itself. Without the creation of institutions like workers councils and neighbourhood councils, which provide the necessary space for human development through practice, the battle of ideas lacks a real basis for the development (‘both individual and collective’) of new socialist subjects. Indeed, this mode of regulation requires a state that supports this struggle ideologically, economically and militarily and thus serves as the midwife for the birth of the new society.

But, what do we mean by the state? Do we mean the old state or the emerging new state based upon workers councils and neighbourhood councils as its cells? How could the old infected state whose very institutions involve a ‘systematic and hierarchic division of labour’—a state which has the character of a public force organized for social enslavement, of an engine of class despotism—possibly be part of the socialist mode of regulation?


Marx and Engels grasped that the working class ‘cannot simply lay hold of the ready-made state machinery, and use it for its own purpose.’ At last, Marx proclaimed, following what he saw as the spontaneous discovery by workers in the Paris Commune of an alternative form of state—a new democratic and decentralized state where the legitimate functions of the state were to be ‘wrested from an authority usurping pre-eminence over society itself, and restored to the responsible agents of society.’ At last, the necessary form of the workers’ state has been discovered: the Commune (which combined legislative and executive functions) was ‘the political form at last discovered under which to work out the economical emancipation of Labour.’ Here was the state which would ‘serve as a lever for uprooting the economical foundations upon which rests the existence of classes, and therefore of class-rule.’

The commune form represented the destruction of centralized state power insofar as that state stands above society. Marx called it ‘the reabsorption of the state power by society as its own living forces instead of as forces controlling and subduing it, by the popular masses themselves, forming their own force instead of the organised force of their suppression—the political form of their social emancipation.’ With the conversion of the state ‘from an organ superimposed upon society into one completely subordinate to it,’ self-governing producers thus wield the state for their own purposes, continuously changing both circumstances and themselves.

This new type of state, based upon direct protagonistic democracy in workplace and community, is indeed essential for the development of socialism as an organic system. Not only does it permit the unleashing of tacit knowledge and popular energy to link the capacities of people to communal needs and purposes but it has as its joint product new social subjects with new capacities, pride and dignity. With the transparency that is necessary for any control from below, those councils in workplaces and communities can police waste, sabotage and other attempts to reverse the process effectively; and, this too, reinforces the sense that the process belongs to the people and is not alien to and above them.

Yet, that new state does not drop from the sky. For one, given the effects of the ‘education, tradition and habit’ of those formed within the old society, we should not be surprised at the power of the old ideas to undermine efforts to build the new state from below. Although people transform themselves through their practice in workers and communal councils, they do so in small units and the spontaneous focus of these cells of the new state inevitably will be one of localism and self-interest (both individual and collective). The development of solidarity and a concept of community that goes beyond the local to other communities and workplaces (and beyond the self-interest that is manifested as consumerism) will tend to emerge only through practice.

These cells, of course, need to be connected if they are to emerge as the new state. They need to develop horizontal and vertical links with other workplaces and communities (as well as with bodies which consolidate these). But the creation of such links through the delegation of spokespersons on their behalf is not the same as the development of solidarity that transcends local self-interest. It takes time before the concept of the whole develops organically in these units and is internalized. In short, although the course of development of socialism as an organic system requires the creation of links based upon solidarity from below and the acceptance of collective democracy that transcends the particular, that process cannot be instantaneous. Accordingly, the new state is not capable initially of making essential decisions that require concentration and coordination of forces.

In contrast, the old state is more likely to be able to see the overall picture at the outset. With the presence of revolutionary actors in the government of the old state, it is possible to confront not only individual capitals but the power of capital as a whole. This is essential because the process of subordinating capital requires the working class to take the power of the existing state away from capital (and thereby to remove its access to the military forces of the state). This is the strength of the old state; it is well situated to identify critical bottlenecks and places for initiatives that require a concentration of forces (including actions to defend the process militarily against internal and external enemies determined to reverse every inroad). Can we imagine building a new society without taking the existing power away from those who possess it in the old society? In contrast to modern fantasists, Marx understood that ‘the transfer of the organized forces of society, viz., the state power, from capitalists and landlords to the producers themselves’ is necessary; he understood that you cannot change the world without taking power.

However, as might be expected from this ‘engine of despotism,’ with its ‘systematic and hierarchic division of labour’ and ‘ready-made state machinery,’ the old state has the tendency to act from above to change circumstances for people rather than to foster revolutionary practice. That state remains above society; it divides society into two parts, one part of which is superior to society and which would bestow socialism as a gift to an underlying population. How could the old hierarchical state—even if made more democratic—foster the key link of human development and practice? Inherent in the logic of representative democracy is the separation of governing from the governed. Thus, rather than the necessary involvement of people which ‘ensures their complete development, both individual and collective,’ the spontaneous tendency of such a state is to reproduce ‘the delusion as if administration and political governing were mysteries, transcendent functions only to be trusted to the hands of a trained caste.’ The faces may change in the legislative branch, but the face of the old state to those below is that of the functionary, ‘an authority usurping pre-eminence over society itself.’ That is precisely why the Commune’s combination of legislative and executive bodies is so central to the development of a state which is society’s ‘own living forces instead of… forces controlling and subduing it.’

During the interregnum when the old state cannot yet die and the new state is not yet able to stand upon its own feet, a great many morbid symptoms appear. Both states are necessary at the outset for the subordination of the old society and the nurturing of the new. However, the inherent tension between the top-down orientation from within the old state and the bottom-up emphasis of the worker and community councils is obvious. In their interaction over a period of indeterminate length, each state will tend to deform the other.

Thus, the desire on the part of revolutionaries in the old state to enact national policies according to a predetermined timetable, for example, tends toward the creation of uniform rules which ignore differences in the history and practices of the cells of the emerging state from below. Both in those cases where organic development is lagging and those where it is more advanced, the effect of demands placed by the old state upon the new shoots will tend to deform their development, as the impatience of functionaries of the old state will either turn the cells of the new into instruments of the old state, or impose a uniformity that tends to reverse unique advances and thereby to discourage initiative and enthusiasm.

Nor, viewed from the other angle, can the old state easily achieve goals of coherent planning, balance and equality when worker and communal councils assert their right to self-determination. As long as these local units insist upon their unique character and the right to pursue their own collective self-interest without interference, the tendency will be to foster relations of exchange (the quid pro quo), inequality and a lack of solidarity. Here, again, the combination of the two states produces incoherence rather than the best of both worlds.

In the context of growing tension and crises produced by the interaction of two diametrically opposed systems, there will be those in the old state who see the solution as the enforcement of power from above. Similarly, there will be those in the new cells who will see the solution as the removal of any authority above the individual unit in order to permit the unfettered pursuit of their particular collective interest. Both those tendencies must be struggled against because each leads to a different deformation of the socialist triangle of social production organized by workers, using socially owned means of production for the purpose of satisfying social needs.

The socialist mode of regulation requires a combination of revolutionary actors within both the old state and the new. Within the old state, it is essential that the policies pursued focus upon both the changing of circumstances and the changing of human beings; this calls for the rejection of capitalist measures of accounting and efficiency and their replacement by a concept of socialist accounting which explicitly recognizes the joint product which emerges from the key link of human development and practice. Within the cells of the new socialist state, on the other hand, the struggle must be against the defects associated with the self-orientation inherited from the old society. In both workplaces and communities, it is essential to find ways to build solidarity with other communities and society as a whole and to develop the understanding that the free development of each has as its condition the free development of all.

In short, the socialist mode of regulation involves a combination of the nurturing of the new state and the withering away of the old. In this process, there is a natural alliance within both the old and the new, not with the goal of achieving a balance between the two states, but unified in the commitment toward building a new socialism oriented explicitly toward human development and defined by the socialist triangle.

The state and the struggle for socialism


This combination of old and new states, however, is not only essential for ensuring the reproduction of socialist relations. A struggle against one-sidedness must be at the core of a strategy to end capitalism and to build socialism. Some people, however, focus only upon the new state (or, if you will, the ‘Unstate’) and reject the idea of using the old state. ‘The very notion that society can be changed through the winning of state power,’ Holloway argues, is the source of all our sense of betrayal; we need to understand, he announces, that ‘to struggle through the state is to become involved in the active process of defeating yourself.’ Why? Because ‘once the logic of power is adopted, the struggle against power is already lost.’ And, why even try? After all, the existing state cannot ‘be made to function in the interests of the working class’ because as a capitalist state ‘its own continued existence is tied to the reproduction of capitalist social relations as a whole.’ The state is ‘just one node in a web of social relations’ and, indeed, is ‘not the locus of power that it appears to be.’

From this perspective, the need to use the state (the armed ‘node’) to rip apart that web of social relations is just so old fashioned—so nineteenth and twentieth century. Forget the military, police, judicial and legislative apparatus now at the disposal of capital. The alternative to capital’s power is already there: ‘ubiquitous power implies ubiquitous resistance. Ubiquitous yes implies ubiquitous no.’ With the Hegelian magic by which things can be miraculously transformed into their opposites (as long as we don’t watch too closely), we come to understand that electoral abstention is victory, lack of leadership is leadership, and the ‘Many’ (the multiplicity of negative struggles against capitalism) is by definition ‘One.’ Negating the existing state through the mind means that it continues in the hands of capital in reality.

The other form of one-sidedness focuses exclusively upon the capture of the old state. Whether choosing the electoral road or invoking glorious victories of the past to support a direct assault upon state power, from this perspective the process of building the institutions and practices characteristic of the new state must be subordinated to the principal task. Social movements essential for the organic development of a new socialist consciousness based upon practice are viewed instrumentally—as fodder for election committees or as the source of cadres for the party. Subordinate, subordinate—that is holy Moses and the prophets! Thus, whether due to the imperatives of electoral rhythm or to the perceived need to rehearse military discipline, the tendency of parties fixated upon the old state is to draw the lifeblood from the incipient elements of the new state and to suppress within their own ranks those who would argue otherwise.

According to Marta Harnecker, this lack of respect for the autonomous development of popular movements was characteristic of elements of the political left in Latin America and brought with it a ‘verticalism, which cancels out people’s initiative’ and a ‘traditional narrow conception of politics’ which ‘tends to reduce politics to the struggle that has to do with political-legal institutions and to exaggerate the role of the state.’ And, the tendency for ‘hierarchization’ is the kernel of truth, too, in Holloway’s argument that the party, ‘whether vanguardist or parliamentary,’ subordinates ‘the myriad forms of class struggle to the overriding aim of gaining control of the state.’

However, rather than inherent in a party as such, this ‘hegemonist’ characteristic is precisely the result of a one-sidedness focused upon the old state. A different left is possible. As Harnecker argues, to build the left essential for socialism for the twenty-first century, we have to change the traditional vision of politics and overcome the narrow definition of power. The new political instrument must grasp the importance of practice for developing consciousness and capacities, needs to learn to listen to popular movements and to respect and nourish them. But it also has a special role—it should not ‘try to gather to its bosom all the legitimate representatives of struggles for emancipation but should strive to coordinate their practices into a single political project’—i.e., to create the spaces where they can learn from each other.

There is an organic link between state and party, and a party which recognizes the necessity for the articulation of old and new state in the process of building socialism differs substantially from one which focuses solely upon the capture of the old state. It is necessarily ‘a political organization which, as it advances a national programme which enables broad sectors of society to rally round the same battle standard, also helps these sectors to transform themselves into the active subjects building the new society for which the battle is being waged.’ In short, the party that is needed is one that learns to walk on two legs.

Two sides, two struggles: a party determined to defeat capital and to build the new state from below must always be consciousness of the danger of one-sidedness. Thus, if crises within capitalism propel a political organization into government, it must not only use that opportunity to defeat the logic of capital and to reduce capital’s power over the old state but also to use the power it has to foster the accelerated development of the sprouts of the new state. And, if conditions are not such as to permit a party to grasp the reins of power in the old state, then it must work to create those conditions by encouraging the autonomous development of social movements through which people can develop their powers and capacities and by building unity among them based upon recognition of difference.

Thus, just as a socialist mode of regulation requires the articulation of old and new state in the process of building socialism as an organic system, so also must we walk on two legs in order to defeat capital and to build collective power. And, at no time is it more possible to demonstrate clearly the gap between the logic of capital and the logic of human development than in the intensified class war when capital is in crisis and the nature of capital comes to the surface. It provides the opportunity to shatter the idea that accepting the demands of capital is common sense. But to show there is an alternative we need the vision of a society in which the free development of each is understood as the condition for the free development of all. And we need to reinforce that vision with more than rhetoric. Unless we are creating through our struggles the spaces which prefigure the new society, we face more glorious defeats.

When capital is in crisis, there are always two options—to give in or to move in. If masses are armed with a clear conception of the socialist alternative, they can turn a crisis in capitalism into the crisis of capitalism. Of course, it is possible that, as the result of our ideological disarmament, the current struggles against the capitalist offensive ultimately may lead to a glorious defeat. It is possible but we must take that chance.

Michael A. Lebowitz (1937-2023) taught Marxian Economics and Comparative Economic Systems at Simon Fraser University in British Columbia since 1965. He was directing the programme in Transformative Practice and Human Development at Centro Internacional Miranda (CIM). His latest book is Between Capitalism and Community (New York: Monthly Review Press 2021). His publications can be found at michaelalebowitz.com.
While Canada profited from war in Yemen, China pushed for peace

Ottawa’s largest non-US buyer of arms is Saudi Arabia

Saudi forces take part in military exercises during a visit by Yemeni Prime Minister Khaled Bahah at a military base in Yemen’s southern embattled city of Aden. Photo by Ahmed Farwan/Flickr.

Owen Schalk / April 23, 2023 
https://canadiandimension.com/

One of the most encouraging developments in global affairs right now is China’s mediation of the regional rivalry between Saudi Arabia and Iran, which has seen Beijing join Oman in pushing for peace in the Saudi-led war on Yemen.

The Omani government has been hosting talks between the Saudi-led coalition and Ansar Allah (the Houthis) for many years, a unique position that has been recognized by all participants in the Yemen war. As the only government in the Gulf Cooperation Council (GCC) not to participate in the military conflict, the Omani capital of Muscat has served as neutral ground for all sides to meet and discuss the humanitarian crisis in neighbouring Yemen. Oman’s diplomatic efforts made possible the April 2022 ceasefire, which more recent peace efforts have built upon.

In March of this year, Beijing facilitated the resumption of diplomatic and commercial ties between Saudi Arabia and Iran. Under the umbrella of the Saudi-Iran détente, Beijing also helped negotiate a deal to finally bring the Saudi-led war of aggression in Yemen—which has killed hundreds of thousands of people and imposed famine conditions on huge areas of the country—to a close.

The negotiations have seen Saudi officials fly to Sana’a, effectively acknowledging the authority of the Houthi government that Riyadh and its allies have demeaned as mere proxies of Iran. Saudi Arabia has also agreed to a range of concessions, which include “opening the major port to allow critical supplies into the country, allowing flights into Sana’a, and allowing the government to have access to its currency to pay its workers and stabilize the economy.” The Saudi blockade of Yemen has still not been fully lifted, but these concessions are steps toward alleviating what the United Nations has recognized as “the world’s worst humanitarian crisis.”

Saudi Arabia’s concessions read like an admission of defeat. Despite all the firepower and diplomatic cover Western nations supplied to Riyadh and its allies, they were unable to beat Ansar Allah, a government and movement with genuine popular support in Yemen.

Indeed, the Houthis’ strategy of bringing the war back to Saudi Arabia with drone and rocket retaliations inside Saudi territory seems to have paid off. With Crown Prince Mohammed bin Salman focused on attracting foreign investors for his Vision 2030 project, sporadic reprisals by an enemy that had basically already won were an unnecessary nuisance. As the war ground on, in fact, it seemed to benefit its participants in Washington, Ottawa, and elsewhere more than it served Riyadh.

It should be remembered that Joe Biden campaigned on ending the war in Yemen. His administration abandoned that promise almost immediately and played no part whatsoever in the negotiations that may bring the conflict to an end. In fact, when news of the Saudi-Iran agreement broke, Biden’s CIA Director William Burns paid an unannounced visit to Saudi Arabia to express Washington’s frustration with Riyadh for seeking rapprochement in the region.

US arms sales to the kingdom made Washington an active participant in the Saudi-led war on Yemen. The same is true of Ottawa, whose largest non-US buyer of arms is Saudi Arabia. Though Ottawa claimed that weapons from Canada were not used in assaults on Yemen, photographic evidence revealed this to be a lie.

Despite being exposed lying about Canada’s participation in the Yemen war, the Trudeau government continued to increase arms sales to Saudi Arabia, jumping from $1.3 billion in 2020 to $1.7 billion in 2021. During the same period, a pair of UN reports directly blamed Canada for fuelling the war through its arms exports to Saudi Arabia. Again, this played no role in Canada’s policy toward the Saudis.

In March, a document obtained by The Breach revealed how Ottawa views Saudi Arabia behind closed doors: as a crucial provider of cheap oil, a source of profits for Canadian companies, and a bulwark of Western power in the West Asian region. The document shows that the Trudeau government considers arms sales to and military cooperation with Saudi Arabia to be a positive thing, as this policy “reduce[s] future requirements for large scale Western military missions.”

Alongside the US and European powers, Canada is an active belligerent in the war in Yemen. Arms companies in Canada profited from selling weapons to the conflict’s aggressor, while Ottawa facilitated the flow of blood money by approving an enormous amount of arms export permits despite evidence that Canadian arms were being used in Yemen.

By contrast, Beijing facilitated negotiations, dialogue, and a potential end to the horrors of the almost ten-year war. It’s difficult to imagine a starker contrast.

Owen Schalk is a writer from Manitoba. His book on Canada’s role in the war in Afghanistan will be released by Lorimer in September. You can preorder it here. To see more of his work, visit www.owenschalk.com.
PAKISTAN
HRCP report

DAWN
Editorial 


IN its flagship annual report on the state of human rights in the country, the Human Rights Commission of Pakistan has painted a sorry picture of where the state actually stands — more than 75 years after independence — on civil liberties, religious freedoms and other fundamental human rights guaranteed by the Constitution. The report, which examines the rights situation in the country in 2022, is a blunt reminder of how the pillars of state — the legislature, judiciary and the executive — have failed in their duty to protect citizens from violence and political and economic exploitation. Particularly at risk are such vulnerable groups as religious minorities, women, sub-national groups, workers and children, while state institutions continue to violate each other’s territory, undermining their institutional capability and credibility. The report specifies how the (ongoing) political and economic turmoil in the country has had a disastrous impact on the human rights situation, and points to the resurgence of terrorism that claimed 533 lives last year. The state’s growing intolerance towards dissenting opinions, free speech and the freedom of assembly has resulted in a large number of enforced disappearances — mostly in Balochistan — as well as the arrest of journalists, social media influencers, political workers and politicians linked to the opposition. Many were subjected to custodial torture while some are facing sedition charges.

Likewise, the inability of the state and its different organs to rectify discriminatory legislation and implement the state’s writ and laws to convict perpetrators has led to an escalation in threats to religious freedom and sexual violence against women and children. The scale of violence and discrimination against trans persons was aggravated by the backlash against the hard-won Transgender Persons (Protection of Rights) Act, 2018. Incidents of mob lynching also appear to have risen, underscoring the fact that intolerance and a lack of respect for the laws of the land at the state level have now completely permeated our social and public life. HRCP has been highlighting these deep-rooted issues afflicting our state and society for decades. But successive governments have failed to address them because the protection of vulnerable segments of society and human rights doesn’t figure on the agenda of political parties. It, therefore, isn’t surprising that, as pointed out by HRCP chairperson Hina Jilani, the human rights community is losing the space which it had gained after a long struggle.

Published in Dawn, April 28th, 2023
‘Taliban consulted Gen Bajwa before reaching out to India’


WASHINGTON: Taliban Fore­ign Minister Amir Khan Muttaqi had a detailed meeting with Pakistan’s former army chief Gen Qamar Javed Bajwa before asking India to send back its diplomats and technical staff to Kabul, says a new book on Afghanistan’s de facto rulers.

The Return of the Taliban reveals “the pivotal decisions leading to the Taliban’s seizure of power” and describes “how as rulers they struggle to reconcile pressures for transition with their rigid ideology”, said Marvin G. Weinbaum, the senior scholar of South Asian affairs in Washington.

The book is authored by Hassan Abbas, who teaches international relations at the National Defence University (NDU), Washington, and will be released in the US later this week.

India’s return to Kabul “could not have happened without Pakistan — and Pakistan acted this way because it just might open up prospects of some aid for the Taliban in Afghanistan,” Mr Abbas writes, arguing that Pakistan is as desperate about getting financial support to run Afghanistan as the Taliban themselves.

Upcoming book claims Kabul wants to mend fences with New Delhi for sake of ‘international legitimacy and recognition’

The book points out that India has strategic interests in Afghanistan, although it notes that unlike Russia and China, India had cut off diplomatic ties with Afghanistan after the Taliban takeover.

But the book also notes that “India is now seriously reassessing its position and moving towards a balancing act in its effort to engage with the Taliban and help stabilise Afghanistan”.

Discussing why the Taliban are eager to mend ties with India, the book says that “the Taliban desire is simple — international legitimacy and recognition”. Kabul’s new rulers also need “huge external investments … to reconstruct and revive the country” and India has the resources to do so.

To demonstrate Gen Bajwa’s influence in Afghanistan, the book narrates the story of Taliban minister for finance Hidayatullah Badri, who was also known by the name of Gul Agha Ishaqzai, who is said to have suffered at the hands of the Pakistani security apparatus following 9/11.

Later, Mr Muttaqi “personally took him to Gen Bajwa to extend the hand of friendship. Only Mr Bajwa’s favorable nod gave him the opportunity” to become the country’s finance minister, the book claims.

The book also discusses former ISI chief Faiz Hamid’s visit to Kabul soon after the Taliban takeover, claiming that Foreign Office had advised Gen Hamid to stay at the Pakistan embassy in Kabul, “but the overconfident spy chief dismissed it”.

Later, at a meeting with Pakistani politicians, including Foreign Minister Bilawal Bhutto-Zardari, he defended his action saying that US and Chinese intelligence chiefs had also visited Kabul around then.

He was reminded that “he was the only one photographed” and “photographs and video clips of him sipping tea in the Serena Hotel, Kabul, went viral”.

The book argues that the “visuals provided evidence of the huge influence” Pakistan had on the Taliban and hurt Pakistan as well as the Taliban.

The book also reviews the growing influence of the IS militant group in Afghanistan, noting that from August 2021, when the Taliban captured Kabul, to August 2022 it claimed responsibility for 262 attacks in the country.

“This trend was an important agenda item in the conversation between ISI chief Lt Gen Nadeem Anjum, and CIA Director William Burns in early May 2022, in Washington. The Pakistani delegation included the former ISI chief Gen Hamid as well,” the book claims.

“Mr Burns told them that at this rate of growth, IS could gain control of 20 per cent of Afghanistan by mid-2023. In response, Gen Anjum stressed the need for targeting (the group’s) top leadership … and intelligence sharing.”

The book says that at the end of the meeting: “both sides reached an interesting conclusion, … the Afghan Taliban are no longer a primary threat to the national security of the US and Afghanistan’s neighboring countries.” It’s ISIS.

The book claims that in the early days of the Taliban takeover, Gen Hamid requested the Taliban high command to “offer both Abdullah [Abdullah] and Hamid Karzai some high-sounding positions” but they did not agree to do so.

The book also underlines China’s desire to stay engaged with the Taliban regime, noting that “China not only kept its embassy open but also welcomed the Taliban’s new status” and urged the UN Security Council to unfreeze Afghanistan’s funds.

Published in Dawn, April 26th, 2023